Remy Maduit | Authors published
THE EUROPE FORUM
Can the EU Be a Federal Democracy?
Assessing the Horizontal and Vertical Dimension of the EU Government from a Comparative Perspective
Jared Sonnicksen is a Professor of Political and Administrative Science,
The University of Konstanz, Department of Politics and Management, Germany.
Volume I, Issue 1, 2022
The Europe Forum
a Mauduit Study Forums’ Journal
Remy Mauduit, Editor-in-Chief
Sonnicksen, Jared (2021) Can the EU Be a Federal Democracy? Assessing the Horizontal and Vertical Dimension of the EU Government from Comparative Perspective, Comparative European Politics, DOI: 10.1057/s41295-021-00265-2.
ARTICLE INFORMATION
Article history
Keywords
Democracy
European Union
Federalism
Government
Separation of powers
ABSTRACT
The European Union remains an ambivalent polity. This uncertainty complicates the assessment of its democratic and federal quality. Drawing on comparative federalism research can contribute not only to making sense of whether, or rather, which kind of federalism the EU has developed. It can also enable addressing such a compounded, but a necessary inquiry into the federal and democratic character of the EU and how to ascertain which type of democratic government for which type of federal union may be appropriate. The article first elaborates a framework to assess the dimensions of federal and democratic government, drawing on comparative federalism research to delineate basic types of federal democracy. Here, the democratic dimension of government is taken as referring primarily to the horizontal division of powers (among ‘branches’) of government, the federal dimension to the vertical division of powers (among ‘levels’) of governments. The framework is applied to the government of the EU to gauge its type(s) of a division of power arrangements and the interlinkages between them. Finally, the discussion reflects on whether or rather how the EU could comprise a federal democracy, especially in light of recent crisis challenges and subsequent institutional developments in EU governance.
The European Union has experienced far-reaching integration in multiple policy areas, expanded powers, and even the introduction of Union citizenship. Yet much reticence remains to view the EU as a conventional political system and a federal one in particular. Varying, and in parts conflicting, definitions and preferences abound about what the EU is and should be. Recent and current crises have only intensified political challenges to the EU, its member-state governments, and citizenries: from the Euro crisis and the ‘migration’ or rather ‘Schengen’ crisis, to the recent ‘Brexit’ and the ongoing Coronavirus/COVID-19 pandemic. In short, EU politics and policy challenges repeatedly trigger polity ones, confronting the EU again in the pending Conference on the Future of Europe. [1]
The EU has long comprised an ambivalent, but also a ‘contested polity’. [2] This complicates the management of many policy issues, but also the very evaluation of its democratic quality and the proper approach to redress its deficit. [3] Were one to still conceive the EU as an international organization, albeit sui-generis, this may lead to particular conclusions: e.g. that either it is sufficiently democratic (as much, if not more than international organizations) or rather that its range of activity and powers have ‘gone too far’. However, matters are more complex. The EU has surely evolved into a unique arrangement of multilevel governance but has also taken on qualities of a system of government for one and of a federal system for another.
Federation emerged as one goal or leitmotif of European integration from the outset. [4] European federalist visions have met with and still face much opposition. The widespread reluctance, and for many aversions, to using the notorious ‘f-word’ for the EU is reflected in recurring phases of treaty reforms and finalité debates, and not least while dealing with crises. [5] Yet regardless of the normative or political (un)desirability of EU federalism, there is much reason to conclude, as others already have at earlier phases of European integration [6], that the EU amounts to a federal arrangement given its legal, structural, and functional development. However, this inference alone does not answer which kind of federalism the EU has. Gaining more clarity on this question is warranted to comprehend the EU better. [7] It may also provide an orientation for further analysis of EU reforms and democratization in particular. The crises of recent further underscore the relevance of these analytical questions. [8]
As recent scholarship in comparative federalism has pointed out, the relationship between democracy and federalism cannot be taken for granted. [9] The simple equation of ‘more federalism’ yielding ‘more democracy’ does not add up. For one, federal systems, like democratic governments, vary substantially. For another, democratic and federal elements or features can be combined or interlinked in one system in different ways that have implications for how democratic and federal governments work. Comparative work on federalism and democracy and their interlinkage or coupling can provide a fruitful approach to navigating a compounded but necessary inquiry into the federal and democratic character of the EU and its system of government. [10]
The following aims are first to elaborate on the distinct dimensions of federal and democratic government, and the basic interlinkage or coupling in particular. The focus here is institutional and on the structural-functional organization of these two dimensions of government. The democratic dimension is taken here to refer primarily to the horizontal division of powers (among ‘branches’) of government, and the federal dimension chiefly to the vertical division of powers (among ‘levels’) of governments. Basic types of polities combining federalism and democracy are outlined. Thirdly, building on this analytical framework, the horizontal and vertical dimensions of the government of the EU are then addressed compactly. Admittedly, much of the complexity of the EU is reduced, though not oversimplified. This endeavor captures the EU’s type(s) of democratic and federal arrangements and their combination to a pattern—or patterns—of federal democracy. Finally, drawing on the insights gained by taking this comparative federal–democratic perspective, the EU polity will be reflected with a view on whether or how it could better meet the conditions of a federal democracy.
Federal and democratic government: distinct, but interlinked
There is a long-standing notion that federalism, with its separation of powers between levels of government, is inherently compatible with and even strengthens democratic government. [11] It also appears to maintain considerable sway in the present. Indicative of this, as one noteworthy example, is Lijphart’s [12] seminal work comparing democratic governments, and its ‘consensus model’ of democracy in particular, for which decentralized or federal government, is among the definitive features (i.e. federalism is subsumed under the consensus-democratic type). In the EU as well, federalism and ‘federalization’ have often been discussed as necessary prerequisites precisely for achieving democratization. [13] However, without delving further theoretically, the world of actual government shows that democracies need not be federal (most democracies, including EU member states, are not), while federal systems are not democratic [14], nor do they inevitably enhance democracy. Particularly this point proves highly relevant to the federalism developed in the EU (addressed further on). In short, the relationship between federalism and democracy is complex. This provides a conceptual point of departure for framing different federal democracies.
Rather than viewing them as part of one particular model of government, it is necessary first to conceive of federalism and democracy as distinct dimensions of government. While both have separation of powers as a core principle in common, each dimension involves different logic of dividing powers and of organizing structures and functions of government. In principle and practice, federalism and democracy each have their variations in structural features and modes of operation relating to how powers are distributed: e.g. ranging from separated or shared; more towards autonomy and competition or rather cooperation, negotiation, and consensus. [15] When combining the two regimes’ dimensions into a federal democracy, the surefire result is a complex multidimensional polity. This becomes apparent with a closer view of these two different dimensions of distributing powers.
First, in federalism, the division can be construed as principally vertical between levels of government: i.e. between the federal (or otherwise denoted superordinate) level of government and the governments of the constituent units. Unitary systems surely vary in terms of centralization or decentralization. However, federalism, according to the widely referenced concept by Elazar, is per se based on ‘non-centralization’. [16] Irrespective of whether certain policy areas or processes are or become centralized or not, federal policies are necessarily distinguished by ‘a constitutionally structured dispersion of power’, and thus an elemental diversity. [17] The constituent units (e.g. cantons, provinces, or states) are aggregated in one polity, yet persist in their own right.
This constitutive distribution of powers between levels of government varies, in a most basic distinction, between separating and sharing powers. Keeping with the structural focus here, we may draw from comparative federalism research two ideal-typical models of dual and cooperative federalism, with the former more prone to the separation and the latter to sharing of powers. [18] This dichotomy can pertain to areas of policy competence (e.g. defense, monetary, infrastructure, education, welfare, etc.) as well as governmental functions (e.g. legislating, implementation, taxation, expenditures, etc.). Dual federalism, where different levels are responsible for different policy areas within their jurisdictions exemplifies separation. Cooperative federalism emphasizes sharing. This may entail constitutionally prescribed or otherwise institutionalized cross-level responsibilities for certain policy areas or rather a division of labor in the exercise of functions (e.g. one level is primarily responsible for legislating and the other for implementing policy). The most intensive forms of cooperative federalism are cases of ‘joint decision-making’ [19], with a cross-level interlocking between the governments at different levels whose consensus is required to reach decisions in those areas prescribing mandatory cooperation. [20]
Second, regarding democracy as a dimension of government, the division of powers can be conceived as chiefly horizontal between branches of government. While authoritarian or other non-democratic systems can exhibit separated institutions with ‘checks and balances or even multiple ‘veto players’ [21], democratic governments and modern representative democracies, in particular, are fundamentally distinguished by free-and-fair popular elections. Maintaining again a structural–institutional focus, of particular concern, are the elected institutions of the executive and legislative branches. The organization of executive-legislative relations and their underlying division of powers pose the primary basis for differentiating types of democratic governments.
Here, we may also draw from comparative research two ideal-typical forms of democratic government. Akin to federal types outlined above, we can distinguish them by their predisposition to separate or share powers between the executive and legislative branches, namely presidential and parliamentary government, respectively. [22] Characteristic of the presidential type is separate elections of the chief executive and the legislature for fixed terms of office, while parliamentary systems in effect fuse the two in that the heads of government along with their cabinets are elected (formally or de facto) by parliament and depend on its confidence to govern. As a paramount distinguishing feature, the parliament in parliamentary governments, its majority specifically, can remove the (head of) government by a vote of no confidence, whereas the legislature’s majority typically cannot depose chief executives in presidential systems. [23] Further typical features underscoring the predispositions towards separation or sharing of powers include, for example, the lack of powers to dissolve the legislature in presidential government, a prerogative typically afforded executives in parliamentary systems, in which compatibility between legislative mandate and executive office is usually (but not in all cases) permissible, but not in the presidential type.
As with the dual and cooperative types of the federal government, these basic types of democratic government do not determine their policy outcomes. They do, however, matter for particular patterns of politics. The horizontal division of powers between the executive and legislative—i.e. as rather strictly separated (presidential) or rather fused power-sharing (parliamentary)—coincides with how political decision-making and contestation unfold [24]: e.g. whether like ‘government-versus-opposition’ dynamics and cohesive party discipline, typically parliamentary or by variable cross-branch and cross-party coalitions on an ad hoc, case-by-case basis, typically presidential.
Thirdly, relations between branches and levels of government surely differ according to the respective features of the horizontal and vertical dimensions of government. Building on these premises, we can conceptualize different institutional arrangements combining federal and democratic government, i.e. composite types of federal democracy. The basic federal and democratic features can be construed, again, as spanning from rather a separation to rather sharing of powers. To delineate these types, Benz has proposed a concept of coupling, which refers to the type and degree of structural and functional interlinkages between institutions and arenas of democratic and federal politics. [25] In the next step, I adopt this framework, with a focus on institutional, structural-functional features, i.e. on branches and levels of government. [26]
We may summarize two basic types of coupling between the federal and democratic dimensions of government as uncoupled and tightly coupled, while a third rather mixed type is referred to as loose coupling (ibid). First, uncoupled applies to arrangements of stricter separation of powers between the executive and legislative branches of government as in a presidential democracy for one, and separation of powers among and with disjointed or few institutionalized interlinkages between levels of government as in dual federalism for another. The USA, a typical case in comparative politics both for presidential democracy and dual federalism, comes closest to the uncoupled ideal type. This is underlined further by bicameralism at the federal level, where the second chamber, the Senate, comprises popularly elected senators: i.e. not delegated by, but ‘detached’ from, state-level governments. Cooperation transpires even under such manifold separation of powers, but tensions arise, especially in addressing cross-jurisdictional/cross-border problems. Deadlocks are prone to result, but can be resolved through consensus agreements or, failing that, then ‘escaped’ for instance by different levels of government resorting to unilateral actions within their ambits.
Tightly coupled democratic and federal dimensions of government conversely implicate more intense interlinkage in multiple regards. This combination entails more sharing and even blending between executive and legislative, as in a parliamentary democracy, and is more cooperation and interdependence oriented, as in cooperative and especially joint decision-making federalism, with multiple institutionalized interlinkages between levels of government. The Federal Republic of Germany, as a parliamentary democracy with a nearly unparalleled extent of joint decision-making, represents a prototypical case of a tightly coupled federal democracy. This is also underlined by its Council model of a second chamber, the Bundesrat, in which members of state (Land) governments (i.e. the executive) are represented and co-decide on a large share of federal legislation. Here, tensions also typically emerge in cases of cross-level cooperation. Representatives of different governments may voluntarily or be required to cooperate, but remain responsible to parliamentary majorities of their respective parliaments, so that the logic of competitive parliamentary government can ‘interfere’ with federal cooperation. [27] In contrast to the uncoupled variant, when cooperation and especially joint decision-making is required, failure to reach consensus results in deadlock at all levels, since a reversion to unilateral action within the levels of government is precluded.
The intermediary concept of loose coupling refers to processes of interaction in federal democracies that, structurally, may conform either to a tightly coupled or uncoupled type. As to the division of powers, this variant is construed here as a combination of one dimension of government based on stricter separation and one more on sharing of powers. Loose coupling entails interaction and cooperation between governments but in flexible institutional arrangements, often underlined by voluntary coordination and opportunities for opt-outs. Canada provides a concrete example of a fused-powers system as (‘Westminster’) parliamentary democracy for one, and with little formal structural interlinkage between provinces and federal government for another, but with routinized intergovernmental relations and conferences for cooperative policy-making. Switzerland represents a separation-of-powers government (i.e. the parliament cannot depose the Executive Council, Bundesrat; there is no ‘government vs. opposition’ between the two branches), yet with an array of processes linking levels of government together for cross-level policy coordination and administration.
While patterns of governing differ within types, individual cases, policy areas, or over time, this framework captures several composite types of democracy and federalism (see Fig. 1). This framework not only provides a fruitful approach to comparing established federal democracies. Applying it to the EU also can contribute to determining more precisely what kind of system of multilevel, division-of-powers government has developed. This may facilitate assessing normative implications of incongruences or ‘mismatches’, as when federal governance diverges from or exceeds the democratic government dimension and its capacity for commensurate legitimation.
Fig. 1
Combinations of the democratic and federal government. Own revised depiction, adapted from the aforementioned illustrative cases (Canada, Germany, Switzerland, United States) elaborated further in Benz (2009, 2020).
EU government in a multilevel system
The following revisits the EU polity based on the framework of types of federal democracies drawn above. Rather than chart the European Union in its entirety as a political system [28], the purpose is to capture the organization of branches and levels of government, with a specific view to determining, or approximating, its type of federal democracy. The horizontal dimension of government and the division of powers among the main governing EU institutions are briefly re-examined. In a second step, a condensed depiction of the vertical division of powers between levels in the EU is provided. Subsequently, a composite pattern of EU federal–democratic government is assessed and critically engaged considering more recent developments in European governance.
Branches of government in the EU
The EU may lack a government in the strict or conventional sense. However, the main institutions at the EU level carry out many typical functions of government and are embedded in a horizontal division of powers. This EU government encompasses ‘branches’ with separation of powers and ‘checks and balances’. In structural and functional terms, the Commission serves as an executive-type body, responsible for proposing legislation and monitoring subsequent implementation, and is supranational. The European Council, consisting of heads of state and government, likewise carries out executive functions, setting broader guidelines in particular, and is chiefly intergovernmental. The European Parliament (EP) and the Council of Ministers (Council) deliberate and decide on legislative acts, forming a legislative ‘branch’ that has developed functionally into a bicameral system. [29] This applies especially to areas of ‘co-decision’ or the ‘ordinary’ legislative procedures (most notably, a vast share of areas directly related to regulating the Common Market).
The Council comprises members of national governments, and enjoys decision-making competence in almost all EU governmental areas, but typically must reach broad consensus, and often unanimity. In instances of ‘co-decision’ with the EP, member-state representatives in the Council are decided by a qualified majority. The EP has broad legislative competencies (co-decision is meanwhile the ordinary legislative procedure) and, unlike other EU institutions, direct democratic legitimation via popular elections. Parties in the EP have developed considerable inner-party congruence, with voting on personnel and bills following party lines, though in variable coalitions. [30] Hence, one can attest to strong bicameralism with a popular chamber (EP) and a member-state-based de facto ‘second chamber’ (Council) vis-à-vis an executive (Commission) that starts proposals and ensures their implementation. To determine an EU type of government, however, we need to consider further the relationship between the executive and the legislative branches.
The EU has essentially two chief executives, one in the Commission and one in the European Council, each installed by different procedures and endowed with different responsibilities. Consensus appoints the President of the European Council among the heads of member-state governments and exercises a predominantly coordinative role. Both the appointment of the Commission and its scope of responsibilities (Article 17 TEU) are more complex. To install a Commission President and a college of Commissioners (i.e. ‘cabinet’), (1) member-state governments in the European Council nominate the president and (2) national governments each nominate a further Commissioner, but both (1) and (2) are each subject to an EP vote of assent. [31] The Treaty of Lisbon prescribed the European Council to consider EP elections when nominating the Commission President (Article 17.7 TEU). For some, this seemed to pose a transition towards a parliamentary government. However, this shift has hardly come to fruition, which the EP elections and the European Council’s repeated disregard of the European political parties’ ‘Spitzenkandidaten’ underline further. [32] The relationship between EP and Council to the Commission has remained a non-parliamentary one for additional reasons.
Unlike parliamentary systems, the EP has no effective vote of confidence, but a censure vote requires a two-thirds majority and is limited in its application (Article 234 TFEU). Conversely, the Commission lacks the competencies to discipline either the EP or the Council with votes of confidence or to dissolve either ‘chamber’. Further underlining stricter separation of powers in the EU government is incompatibility, i.e., unlike most parliamentary systems, members of the EP and the Council (member-state governments) cannot simultaneously be part of the Commission. Unsurprisingly, governing in the EU does not conform to politics like ‘government versus opposition’, not even within the EP and even less so among EU institutions (Fig. 2).
Fig. 2
Separation of powers among EU institutions.
EU government entails mutual checks and balances in legislative processes and in the nomination and confirmation of chief executives. The EU institutions depend on one another to govern. However, they maintain stricter separation of powers given membership incompatibility between institutions, lack of executive powers to dissolve legislative institutions, and lack of legislature power to remove executives by a regular-majority vote of no confidence. From this follows that, in the horizontal dimension, the EU government resembles a non-parliamentary, rather presidential type governmental arrangement on the one hand, but bereft of the typically coinciding democratic linkage on the other, a popularly elected chief executive. [33]
Levels of government in the EU
Concerning the vertical dimension, the EU is widely accepted as a paradigmatic case of multilevel governance. [34] The EU treaties refrain from referring to federalism per se, nor do they include explicit references to sovereignty. However, they do exhibit formal indications of not just a multilevel, but even a federal arrangement: for instance, a ‘reservation’ of powers to the member states (e.g. Article 4 TEU, reserving competences not conferred upon the Union to the Member States) in combination with principles of ‘subsidiarity’ and vertical distribution of powers (e.g. Article 5 TEU, by which Union competences ‘are governed by the principle of conferral’). The treaties allocate various political and institutional responsibilities, for instance, by policy area. One may summarize three basic types or ‘patterns’ of competence allocation (and with that, ‘governance modes’), namely supranational, intergovernmental and joint competencies). [35] In supranational areas, i.e. falling only under the ambit of the Union such as trade, competition, and, for ‘Eurozone’ members, currency policy, the responsibility for implementation lies predominantly with Union-level institutions (e.g. the Commission, sometimes the European Central Bank, etc.). In more intergovernmental areas like foreign and security policy, the European Council, Council, and the member states are primarily responsible for deciding—typically by unanimity or broad consensus—and carrying them out. The third main variant refers to areas of joint responsibility between the Union and the member states (see Articles 4, 5, and 6 TFEU), representing by now the largest share of the EU policy.
In areas of joint responsibility especially, the treaties set forth that member states ‘shall adopt all measures of national law necessary to implement legally binding Union acts’ (Article 291.1 TFEU), i.e. implementation at the member-state level. There is a far-reaching multilevel interlinkage of the executive reflected in the rules on administrative cooperation (Article 197 TFEU-L). This means in principle that member-state actors—not only governments but also national and subnational administrations—are decisive in implementing EU law. This responsibility for implementation comes beside the weighty position of member-state governments in EU legislative matters through their incorporation in a de facto ‘second chamber’, the Council. The duty to enforce these processes falls upon the Commission, which ensures the ‘application of the treaties’ (Article 17 TEU) and takes care that Union policies are implemented (see also Fig. 3). Several control and monitoring instruments are at the disposal of the Commission (Article 17.1 TEU; Articles 105, 258, and 259 TFEU), such as the competence to start infringement procedures against non-compliant member states or bring them before the European Court of Justice.
Fig. 3
The multilevel executive and implementation (ordinary legislation).
The Commission and multiple administrative and regulatory agencies linked to it in various ways have developed into a wide-ranging European bureaucracy or Eurocracy. [36] Further European agencies and offices have been established for coordinating and regulating individual policy areas, with variable degrees of (in)dependence and discretion, being loosely or tightly bound to the Commission, other EU institutions, and/or the member states. [37] These institutional and procedural features also point to the development of a multilevel administration and government.
With the transition from the Community to the wider European Union, it has already been concluded that a ‘regulatory federal’ [38] and even ‘executive federal’ [39] system has developed. Surmising moreover from the concise sketch above, the EU vertical division-of-powers dimension encompasses multiple elements of federalism—even if not nominally so. These features range from dualistic separation-of-powers federalism (e.g. conferral of powers to the Union, reservation of other powers to the member states), an extensive scope of cooperative federalism (e.g. many areas prescribing intergovernmental cooperation and coordination), and not least the joint decision and administration of European legal acts. The EU level may lack its own Kompetenz-Kompetenz, in the sense that the EU ‘government’ could alter its scope of powers. [40] However, national governments in federal systems normally also lack the power to unilaterally alter the constitutional distribution of powers.
EU polity: a pattern of mixed federal and limited democratic government
The EU comprises a multilevel system with extensive, though variable vertical separation and sharing of powers. Along with the Commission, many actors from multiple levels and institutions of government are included in implementing European legal acts, taking part, controlling, influencing, and shaping implementation at multiple stages and places. The EU executive can be divided structurally on a horizontal level into a rather supranational part, anchored mainly in the Commission, and an intergovernmental, member-state-oriented part, institutionalized most saliently in the Council and the European Council. The combination of this complexity with variability between supranational, intergovernmental, and community modes of governance in the EU multilevel system allows for its conceptualization in toto as a ‘loosely coupled’ federative arrangement. [Someone can divide structurally the EU executive41] However, governing in the EU far exceeds loose coupling in the passage and implementation of Union legal acts, especially those reached by co-decision, comprising together a system of joint decision-making.
On the one hand, regarding the horizontal dimension, the EU government corresponds with a separation-of-power type system. It is structurally and functionally akin to presidential systems of separation between executive and legislative, though unlike, for example, the US case, without popular elections of the EU executive or second chamber. The EU vertical dimension of government, especially where joint decision-making and administration are concerned, resembles rather the structures and functions of Germany’s tightly coupled cooperative federalism but without an EU-level government responsible to the EP as a popularly elected first chamber. [42] The interlinkage between member-state governments co-deciding EU legislative matters that they subsequently implement at the national level reveals remarkable similarities to the German ‘Bundesrat’ model. However, the EU differs from this case of federal democracy in that, at the EU level, the system of government diverges categorically from parliamentary democracy: i.e. the no-confidence relationship between the legislature and EU chief executives. Indeed, the EU departs from federal democracies in lacking a democratically elected and accountable government altogether (Fig. 4).
Fig. 4
Pattern(s) of EU government between separation and sharing of powers.
Thus, we arrive at a composite picture of the horizontal and vertical organization of branches and levels of government in the EU. While the EU bears striking similarities to other federal systems in various regards, it also exhibits divergences or ‘gaps’ between its federal governance and representative–democratic government. Gauging by established federal democracies, several commensurate democratization reforms could span from, for instance: (1) bringing the EU in line with parliamentary–democratic federalism by which the Commission becomes a government responsible to and removable by an EP majority (e.g. akin to the German tightly coupled model); (2) the direct election of the Commission President in line with a presidential-democratic federal order (e.g. akin to the US uncoupled model, at least at EU level); or (3) maintaining a non-parliamentary, separation-of-powers EU-level government ‘as is’ and rather pursuing democratization by introducing facultative referendums, thus embedding EU governance in the ‘shadow’ of potential plebiscites (e.g. akin to the Swiss ‘loosely coupled’ model). The already-established federalism of the EU warrants consideration of such democratization reforms. But further complexity emerges, for one, given the larger diversity of governance modes in the EU than captured above. For another, changing patterns of governing in the EU raise additional challenges to realizing more democratic federalism.
Changing patterns of governing as federal–democratic challenges
The prior analysis affirms that the community method of governing in the EU (i.e. ordinary legislative procedure with joint decision-making and cooperative-federal implementation) raises concerns about a democratic deficit that has not been resolved. The intergovernmental model of governing, in contrast, would appear much less invasive on the autonomy of member states and thus less demanding of a ‘Europeanized’ democratic legitimation. Common decisions in intergovernmental made-up areas have typically required unanimity and, when barring this, further integration could be reached at least through constructive abstentions and/or the permission of opt-outs. This sort of loosely coupled arrangement has also been likened to modes of ‘treaty federalism’ in the Canadian case. [43] More reliance on this approach to governing could allow for variable, ‘differentiated integration’ [44]: national governments could reach voluntary agreements while maintaining substantial latitude for achieving common goals and without hierarchic enforcement of compliance by the supranational level.
What has complicated, indeed exacerbated, matters in recent years, however, has been precisely the shift to the mode of a ‘new intergovernmentalism’. [45] This pattern has intensified most notably in the currency’s wake, sovereign debt, and wider financial European crises, followed by a so-called ‘migration crisis’ induced by a flux of migration—the EU crisis lying rather with its breakdown in cross-European coordination. The democratic deficit already attributed to ordinary patterns of governing within the Common Market becomes problematic in the intergovernmental mode when it turns coercive. This applies especially to the creation of de novo bodies (e.g. EFSF and ESM) to implement conditionality or austerity policy on fiscally beleaguered member states; these developments have transpired under the conditions of a persistent lack of a common EU welfare regime as a corrective counterpart to integration that one-sidedly favors the market freedoms of people, goods, capital, and services. With the Euro crisis, the EU government did not lead the fiscal and economic governance responses, but national governments. Further austerity and budget consolidation policies determined by the Councils and the strengthening of the Commission’s role in monitoring national compliance have intensified ‘executive federalism’ of the EU, but with no parallel extensions of democratization. [46] This rather propels a further decline in the accountability of European governance to national parliaments or the European Parliament. The failure of national governments to manage common approaches like in the ‘migration crisis’ or current coronavirus pandemic could have severe implications for democratic legitimacy and support for the EU, the ‘integration project’, and even national governments.
From the democratic–federal perspective, a resort to more intergovernmentalism under current conditions in pursuit of further integration can hardly provide a viably legitimate approach. Certainly, the world of democratic federalism does not provide any comparable model or practice. One would search in vain for a democratic federation that has no polity-wide democratically legitimated government, or where subnational governments take over leadership of the polity via intergovernmental conferences. That is unless one looked at looser confederal models of the past, which were also severely more limited in scope and trajectory of powers than is the case in the current EU. [47] If national governments continue to assume leadership at the European level, they would, by any minimal representative-democratic standard, have to take on corresponding responsibility. Under given conditions, though, member-state governments are responsible for their national parliaments and electorates. The latter are structurally and institutionally wholly detached or uncoupled from one another (i.e. citizens do not vote for parliaments of other member states). As a result, and in absence of an EU-level government to elect and, as the case may, reward or sanction, then national elections would also have to serve as a channel for contestation over European-level politics and political (non-)decisions.
Compared with federal democracies, the federalism developed in the EU does not adequately conform to representative–democratic governments. The crisis management of recent years has even exacerbated this deficit. Crises may be the ‘hour of the executive’ in any polity. However, the EU polity lacks an overarching democratic government that may allow for tolerating, not to mention legitimating, a temporary ‘stretch’ of the EU executive, be it the Commission or the Council. At the bottom line, the analysis of how the EU system of government has evolved and recent developments at the latest reveal that to be a federal democracy, the democratization of European federalism appears even more urgent.
Conclusion
The Treaty of Lisbon, the last large-scale revision of the European Treaties, was prescribed to enhance multiple democratically and federally relevant principles. However, the dynamics of EU governments have failed to bring about, for instance, either the transition to the EU parliamentary government or an effective extension of national parliaments. [48] Concerning representative democracy, the requirement of member-state governments to consider EP elections in selecting the Commission President was celebrated as a step toward a parliamentary model. While this would make up for a stark shift away from the EU government’s separation of powers, it also does not appear a realistic prospect. The member-state governments enjoy a preeminent position at the EU level, and the current Commission installed after the EP elections of 2019 confirmed national governments’ willingness and ability to discard European Political Parties’ ‘Spitzenkandidaten’ without ramifications. [49] The Treaty likewise prescribed a commitment to enhancing the position of national parliaments in the EU. However, the concrete inclusion of an Early Warning Mechanism has led neither to the fruition of a ‘virtual third chamber’ [50], nor the expansion of horizontal interparliamentary cooperation that could counteract the long-attested executive dominance in the EU. [51] On the contrary, executive dominance grew not just intensely but also asymmetrically among member states in crises of recent. The result is a rather sobering balance of the EU as a federal democracy.
The comparative federal–democratic framework applied here shows much analytical merit. It has helped to capture the constitution of the horizontal and vertical division of powers in the EU, but also of what kind or type in each dimension. While not a democratic government, the EU institutions make up a system of separation of powers among its branches. The assessment of the vertical dimension does not just reaffirm that the EU is sui generis yet ‘somehow federal’. Of course, the EU remains one of a kind. But comparison reveals that the EU multilevel system corresponds to a large extent to one of legislative and administrative cooperative federalism with joint decision-making. The approach is taken here thus allows for identifying the EU character in comparison with federal democracies: its—hitherto unparalleled—combination of stricter separation of powers at the level of (supra)national government with an arrangement of vertical interlocking and extensive joint decision-making between levels of government. Leaving aside such questions about whether the EU has or even could have a demos or at most demoi [52], it remains difficult but not impossible to assess a commensurate democratization approach.
Complicating matters, though, is that much of multilevel governance in the EU still falls outside of the area of community or joint tasks and respective decision-making modes, and is more intergovernmental. Where intergovernmentalism has predominated, the question of EU-level democracy could long be deemed less pressing, as the autonomy of member states and their democratically elected governments enjoyed safeguards, e.g. through unanimity rules, leverage for opt-outs, and divergences, or resort to voluntary cooperation. Intergovernmental governance in the EU has witnessed a shift in recent years to executive dominance, no less asymmetrically wielded among the member-state governments. Under such conditions, the EU multilevel government not only continues to have a demos- but even demoi-constraining effect.
Whether one subscribes to the concept of the EU as a mixed Union of people and states, one of a compound republic, or rather a confederal association of states where only the co-existence of peoples is possible, the comparative federal–democratic framework adopted here allows, I submit, for us to draw a clearer conclusion: federalism and democracy are out of balance in the EU. For not only has the extent of democratization of the Union government not coincided with the extension of the scope and trajectory of supranational and joint decision EU governance so far. Intergovernmental governance would also appear to exceed its basis of member-state-grounded democratic legitimacy. This reveals a challenge to democratizing an EU government as it stands.
To comprise thus a federal democracy, while many options are conceivable, two basic federal–democratic routes can be summarized. One route implicates specifically federal measures towards uncoupling and returning competencies to the member states where institutions and processes of democratic government—not just complex separation of powers—still live in Europe. Such a step would apply to supranational and ‘communitarized’ areas, but also the intergovernmental arena where formerly loosely coupled governance has taken on a particular pattern of a coercive and asymmetric one. The alternative route European governments could take lies in pursuing fundamental democratization of the EU ‘federal government’, including Europeanization of EP elections and popular control over the EU executive, whether, for example, by its popular election or its more consistent transition towards a parliamentary government elected by and responsible to the EP majority that would likewise have more co-determination in areas that are organized intergovernmentally. Otherwise, the EU and its member states risk remaining stuck to meddling through a system of federalism many still refuse to admit has already been achieved, while failing to fulfill standards of democracy the Treaties, EU institutions, and member-state governments claim to be committed to.
[1]Lefkofridi, Zoe, and Philippe Schmitter. 2015. Transcending or Descending? European Integration in Times of Crisis. European Political Science Review 7 (1): 3–22.
[2] Lord, Christopher. 2001. Assessing Democracy in a Contested Polity. Journal of Common Market Studies 39 (4): 641–661.
[3] De Angelis, Gabriele. 2020. Debating Finalité: Neo-Functional Dilemmas and Institutional Reforms. Comparative European Politics 18 (4): 689–706.
[4] See the Schuman Declaration (1950), e.g.: “The pooling of coal and steel production should immediately provide for the setting up of common foundations for economic development as a first step in the federation of Europe”, (emphasis added).
[5] Borriello, Arthur, and Amandine Crespy. 2015. How Not to Speak the ‘F-word’: Federalism Between Mirage and Imperative in the Euro Crisis. European Journal of Political Research 54 (3): 502–524.
De Angelis, Gabriele. 2020. Debating Finalité: Neo-Functional Dilemmas and Institutional Reforms. Comparative European Politics 18 (4): 689–706.
Pollack, Mark. 2005. Theorizing the European Union: International Organization, Domestic Polity, or Experiment in New Governance? Annual Review of Political Science 8: 357–398.
[6] Börzel, Tanja, and Madeleine Hosli. 2003. Brussels Between Bern and Berlin: Comparative Federalism Meets the European Union. Governance 16 (2): 179–202.
Sbragia, Alberta. 1993. The European Community: A Balancing Act. Publius 23 (3): 23–38.
[7] Fossum, John Erik, and Markus Jachtenfuchs. 2017. Federal Challenges and Challenges to Federalism. Insights From the EU and the Federal States. Journal of European Public Policy 24 (4): 467–485.
[8] For instance, the Conference on the Future of Europe has again placed reforms on the EU political agenda, while after Brexit, the EU has lost a conventionally rather adamant opponent of the ‘F-word’ in Europe, which could (though not necessarily) facilitate the reform debate in this sense.
[9] Benz, Arthur. 2009. Ein gordischer Knoten der Politikwissenschaft? Zur Vereinbarkeit von Föderalismus und Demokratie. Politische Vierteljahresschrift 50 (1): 3–22.
Benz, Arthur. 2020. Föderale Demokratie. Regieren im Spannungsfeld von Interdependenz und Autonomie. Baden-Baden: Nomos.
Burgess, Michael, and Alain-G. Gagnon, eds. 2010. Federal Democracies. London: Routledge.
[10] Id.
[11] Burgess, Michael, and Alain-G. Gagnon, eds. 2010. Federal Democracies. London: Routledge.
Gerring, John, Strom Thacker, and Carola Moreno. 2005. Centripetal Democratic Governance: A Theory and Global Inquiry. American Political Science Review 99 (4): 567–581.
Levy, Jacob. 2007. Federalism, Liberalism, and the Separation of Loyalties. American Political Science Review 101 (3): 459–477.
[12] Lijphart, Arend. 2012. Patterns of Democracy. Government Forms and Performance in Thirty-six Countries, 2nd ed. New Haven: Yale University Press.
[13] Trechsel, Alexander. 2005. How to Federalize the European Union… and Why Bother. Journal of European Public Policy 12 (3): 401–418.
[14] Gibson, Edward. 2013. Boundary Control. Subnational Authoritarianism in Federal Democracies. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
[15] Benz, Arthur. 2020. Föderale Demokratie. Regieren im Spannungsfeld von Interdependenz und Autonomie. Baden-Baden: Nomos.
Burgess, Michael, and Alain-G. Gagnon, eds. 2010. Federal Democracies. London: Routledge.
Hueglin, Thomas, and Alan Fenna. 2015. Comparative Federalism. A Systematic Inquiry, 2nd ed. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
[16] Elazar, Daniel. 1985. Federalism and Consociational Regimes. Publius 15 (2): 17–34.
Elazar, Daniel. 1987. Exploring Federalism. Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press.
[17] Watts, Ronald. 1998. Federalism, Federal Political Systems, and Federations. Annual Review of Political Science 1: 117–137.
[18] Hueglin, Thomas, and Alan Fenna. 2015. Comparative Federalism. A Systematic Inquiry, 2nd ed. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Watts, Ronald. 2006. Origins of Cooperative and Competitive Federalism. In Territory, Democracy, and Justice. Regionalism and Federalism in Western Democracies, ed. Scott Greer, 201–223. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
[19] Scharpf, Fritz. 1988. The Joint-Decision Trap: Lessons from German Federalism and European Integration. Public Administration 66 (3): 239–278.
Scharpf, Fritz. 1997. Games Real Actors. Play Actor Centered Institutionalism in Policy Research. Boulder: Westview.
[20] Of course, the varieties and complexities of federal systems have been reduced here. The joint decision-making concept—see Scharpf et al. (1976)—is an important case in point, which differentiated between systems of compulsory and voluntary cooperation among governments while more recent research has elaborated even further varieties of joint decision-making; see esp. Benz et al. (2016). However, for sake of brevity and concise conceptualization, the analytical framework here foregoes an in-depth elaboration of the sub-variants of basic types of federal systems.
[21] Tsebelis, George. 2002. Veto Players. How Political Institutions Work. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
[22] Lijphart, Arend, ed. 1992. Parliamentary Versus Presidential Government. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Samuels, David, and M Shugart Matthew. 2010. Presidents, Parties, and Prime Ministers: How the Separation of Powers Affects Party Organization and Behavior. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Shugart, Matthew, and John Carey. 1992. Presidents and Assemblies. Constitutional Design and Electoral Dynamics. New York: Cambridge University Press.
There is much discussion in the relevant comparative government literature on demarcations between presidential and parliamentary government and the ‘hybrid’ case of semi-presidential systems (for an overview, see e.g. Fruhstorfer 2016). While the office of head of state is elected popularly, the head of government remains responsible to the parliament and its majority in particular. I view ‘semi-presidential systems here as a subtype of a parliamentary system.
[23] Id.
Huber, John. 1996. The Vote of Confidence in Parliamentary Democracies. American Political Science Review 90 (2): 269–282.
[24] Gerring, John, Strom Thacker, and Carola Moreno. 2009. Are Parliamentary Systems Better? Comparative Political Studies 42 (3): 327–359.
Samuels, David, and M Shugart Matthew. 2010. Presidents, Parties, and Prime Ministers: How the Separation of Powers Affects Party Organization and Behavior. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
[25] Benz, Arthur. 2009. Ein gordischer Knoten der Politikwissenschaft? Zur Vereinbarkeit von Föderalismus und Demokratie. Politische Vierteljahresschrift 50 (1): 3–22.
Benz, Arthur. 2020. Föderale Demokratie. Regieren im Spannungsfeld von Interdependenz und Autonomie. Baden-Baden: Nomos.
Benz, Arthur, and Jared Sonnicksen, eds. 2021. Federal Democracies at Work. Varieties of Complex Government. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
[26] The analytical framework here leaves out other—admittedly highly relevant—features such as intergovernmental relations or, the federal character of the party system, among others, to focus on government.
[27] Lehmbruch, Gerhard. 2000. Parteienwettbewerb im Bundesstaat. Regelsysteme und Spannungslagen im Institutionengefüge der Bundesrepublik Deutschland, 3rd ed. Wiesbaden: Westdeutscher Verlag.
[28] Cini, Michelle, Pérez-Solórzano. Borrágan, and Nieves, eds. 2019. European Union Politics, 6th ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hix, Simon, and Bjørn. Høyland. 2011. The Political System of the European Union, 3rd ed. London: Red Globe Press.
[29] Hagemann, Sara, and Bjørn. Høyland. 2010. Bicameral Politics in the European Union. Journal of Common Market Studies 48 (4): 811–833.
Kreppel, Amie. 2018. Bicameralism and the Balance of Power in EU Legislative Politics. Journal of Legislative Studies 24 (1): 11–33.
[30] Hix, Simon, and Bjørn. Høyland. 2013. Empowerment of the European Parliament. Annual Review of Political Science 16: 171–189.
[31] Nasshoven, Yvonne. 2010. The Appointment of the President of the European Commission. Patterns in Choosing the Head of Europe’s Executive. Baden-Baden: Nomos.
[32] Dawson, Mark. 2019. The Lost Spitzenkandidaten and the Future of European Democracy. Maastricht Journal of European and Comparative Law 26 (6): 731–735.
Hobolt, Sara. 2014. A Vote for the President? The Role of Spitzenkandidaten in the 2014 European Parliament Elections. Journal of European Public Policy 21 (10): 1528–1540.
[33] Fabbrini, Sergio. 2004. Madison in Brussels. The EU and US as Compound Democracies Compared. European Political Science 4 (2): 188–198.
Kreppel, Amie. 2011. Looking ‘Up’, ‘Down’, and ‘Sideways’. Understanding EU Institutions in Context. West European Politics 34 (1): 167–179.
Sonnicksen, Jared. 2017. Democratizing the separation of powers in EU government: The case for presidential. European Law Journal 23 (6): 509–522.
[34] Hooghe, Liesbet, and Gary Marks. 2001. Multi-Level Governance and European Integration. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.
Piattoni, Simona. 2010. The Theory of Multi-Level Governance. Conceptual, Empirical, and Normative Challenges. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
[35] Scharpf, Fritz. 1994. Community and Autonomy: Multi-level policy-making in the European Union. Journal of European Public Policy 1 (2): 219–242.
Héretier, Adrienne, and Martin Rhodes, eds. 2010. New Modes of Governance in Europe. Governing in the Shadow of Hierarchy. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
[36] Kelemen, R. Daniel., and Andrew Tarrant. 2011. The Political Foundations of the Eurocracy. West European Politics 34 (5): 922–947.
[37] Egeberg, Morten, and Jarle Trondal. 2017. Researching European Union Agencies: What Have We Learnt (and Where Do We Go from Here)? Journal of Common Market Studies 55 (4): 675–690.
[38] Kelemen, R. Daniel. 2000. Regulatory Federalism: EU Environmental Regulation in Comparative Perspective. Journal of Public Policy 20 (2): 133–167.
[39] Schütze, Robert. 2010. From Rome to Lisbon. ‘Executive Federalism’ in the (New) European Union. Common Market Law Review 47 (5): 1385–1427.
[40] Beck, Gunnar. 2011. The Lisbon Judgment of the German Constitutional Court, the Primacy of EU Law and the Problem of Kompetenz-Kompetenz: A Conflict between Right and Right in Which There is No Praetor. European Law Journal 17 (4): 470–494.
[41] Benz, Arthur. 2010. The European Union as a Loosely Coupled Multi-Level System. In Handbook on Multi-Level Governance, ed. Henrik Enderlein, Sonja Wälti, and Michael Zürn, 214–226. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
[42] Kreppel, Amie. 2011. Looking ‘Up’, ‘Down’, and ‘Sideways’. Understanding EU Institutions in Context. West European Politics 34 (1): 167–179.
[43] Hueglin, Thomas. 2013. Treaty Federalism as a Model of Policy-Making: Comparing Canada and the European Union. Canadian Public Administration 56 (2): 185–202.
Verdun, Amy. 2016. The Federal Features of the EU: Lessons from Canada. Politics and Governance 4 (3): 100–110.
[44] Fossum, John Erik. 2015. Democracy and Differentiation in Europe. Journal of European Public Policy 22 (6): 799–815.
Schmidt, Vivien. 2019. The future of differentiated integration: A ‘soft-core’, multi-clustered Europe of overlapping policy communities. Comparative European Politics 17 (2): 294–315.
[45] Bickerton, Christopher, Dermot Hodson, and Uwe Puetter. 2015. The New Intergovernmentalism. European Integration in the Post-Maastricht Era. Journal of Common Market Studies 53 (4): 703–722.
[46] Crum, Ben. 2013. Saving the Euro at the Cost of Democracy? Journal of Common Market Studies 51 (4): 614–630.
Fabbrini, Sergio. 2016. The Constitutional Conundrum of the European Union. Journal of European Public Policy 23 (1): 84–100.
[47] Glencross, Andrew. 2009. What Makes the EU Viable? European Integration in the Light of the Antebellum US Experience. Basingstoke: Palgrave.
[48] Bevir, Mark, and Ryan Phillips. 2017. EU Democracy and the Treaty of Lisbon. Comparative European Politics 15 (5): 705–728.
[49] Dawson, Mark. 2019. The Lost Spitzenkandidaten and the Future of European Democracy. Maastricht Journal of European and Comparative Law 26 (6): 731–735.
Heidbreder, Eva, and Daniel Schade. 2019. (Un)settling the Precedent: Contrasting Institutionalisation Dynamics in the Spitzenkandidaten Procedure of 2014 and 2019. Research and Politics. https://doi.org/10.1177/2053168020925975.
[50] Cooper, Ian. 2012. A ‘Virtual Third Chamber’ for the European Union? National Parliaments After the Treaty of Lisbon. West European Politics 25 (3): 441–465.
[51] Bellamy, Richard, and Sandra Kröger. 2016. The Politicization of European Integration: National Parliament and the Democratic Disconnect. Comparative European Politics 14 (2): 125–130.
[52] Nicolaïdis, Kalypso. 2013. European Democracy and Its Crisis. Journal of Common Market Studies 51 (2): 351–369.
Risse, Thomas. 2014. No Demos? Identities and Public Spheres in the Euro Crisis. Journal of Common Market Studies 52 (6): 1207–1215.
Ronzoni, Miriam. 2017. The European Union as a Democracy: Really a Third Way? European Journal of Political Theory 16 (2): 210–234.
.