Remy Maduit | Authors published
INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
& POLITICS
Bringing Morgenthau’s Ethics In
Pluralism, Incommensurability, and the Turn from Fragmentation to Dialogue in IR
Haro L Karkour teaches at the University of Birmingham, UK
Dominik Giese is a Marie-Sklodowska Curie Action Researcher at the University of Hamburg
and the University of Warwick, Germany & UK
Volume I, Issue 1, 2022
International Relations & Politics Forum
a Mauduit Study Forums’ Journal
Remy Mauduit, Editor-in-Chief
Karour, Haro & Giese, Dominik (2020) Bringing Morgenthau’s ethics in pluralism, incommensurability and the turn from fragmentation to dialogue in IR, European Journal of International Relations, DOI: 10.1177/1354066120934044.
ARTICLE INFO
Article history
Disclosure: Dominik Giese received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation program under the Marie Sklodowska-Curie Grant Agreement No 722826.
Keywords
classical realism
dialogue
fragmentation
incommensurability
Hans Morgenthau
IR pluralism
ABSTRACT
Why did IR pluralism end with so many incommensurable camps? (How) can IR be demarcated as a discipline where these camps can find common ground for dialogue without glossing over theoretical pluralism? To answer the first question, the paper argues that Morgenthau’s critique of IR as social science can explain the proliferation of camps in IR pluralism that are incommensurable and cannot engage in dialogue. By transcending the dilemma of politics, as highlighted in Morgenthau’s critique of social science, theories today are ideological camps that give morality an ideological function that justifies their powers-that-be that serve particular means/ends hierarchies. This leads to the proliferation of empirical causal analyses that cannot be debated since they rely on political interests that theory ideologically justifies and offers internal validation. To avoid this problem, the paper answers the second question by proposing to demarcate the discipline through Morgenthau’s concept of ‘interest defined as power’. It argues that demarcating the discipline based on this concept opens room for engaging in dialogue in IR by leaving open the normative debate of means and ends, and thus acts as a bulwark against the proliferation of ideological camps while promoting theoretical pluralism.
There is no one agreed definition of pluralism in International Relations (IR). Pluralism in IR may mean to ‘deprive any methodology of the ability to claim a uniquely scientific status’.[1] It may mean promoting a project of a ‘Global IR’ that is no more dominated by one region or set of (state-based) actors. [2] It may mean ‘expanding the methodological toolkit’ a la analytic eclecticism [3], questioning the dominance of neo-positivist methodology and its delegitimation of other approaches to knowledge production [4], or a more open ‘critical problem solving’ approach. [5] It may mean rejecting the ‘evil’ of isms and in lieu of focusing on ‘mid-range’ theorizing [6], or, by contrast, theoretical exchange. [7] Pluralism may mean avoiding the reproduction of IR as a colonial discipline that neglects important events in world history, such as the Haitian revolution [8], or telling the ‘real story of Europe’ altogether.[9 ] This is by no means an exhaustive list of what pluralism may mean, but enough to show that if ‘isms’ are authoritarian, divisive, and evil, then the state of plural-ism reproduces these ‘camps’ further, with each camp ‘relatively secure today, comfortable knowing that it has a power-based in the field’. [10]
The debate on pluralism in IR is inseparable from the question of what IR, as a discipline, entails and how it is demarcated as a discipline. The question ‘what is IR’ was recently debated in the journal International Relations, following Rosenberg’s [11] seminal paper that called for breaking the discipline out of the ‘prison’ of political science and accounting for the independence of the ‘international’ and its implications for societal multiplicity. Rosenberg’s critics immediately posited his failure to account for the prison of ‘colonial modernity’ in erasing multiplicity from IR [12] and for failing to present a restrictive ‘multiplicity’ that is inclusive enough to ‘encompass all the work that presently goes on in international studies’. [13] Later critics raised similar concerns about Rosenberg’s ‘oddly Westphalian’ conception of IR [14], and suggested thinking about the multiplicity of ‘social, natural and technological spheres’ [15], ‘think[ing] of multiplicity and its consequences far beyond humanity’ [16], and ‘deepening multiplicity’. [17] What is evident here once again is the value of pluralism despite the lack of consensus on what it means, and consequently, what IR, as a discipline, may entail. [18]
This background raises two questions that this paper engages with. First, why did IR pluralism end with so many incommensurable camps? Second, (how) can IR be demarcated as a discipline where these camps can find common ground for dialogue without glossing over theoretical pluralism? To answer the first question, this paper argues that Morgenthau’s critique of IR as social science can explain the proliferation of camps in IR pluralism that are incommensurable and cannot engage in dialogue. A key problem with the IR pluralism debate is that political interests are used as entry points to theory but then legitimized through empirical validation and closed to normative scrutiny. In his critique of IR as social science, Morgenthau warned against this problem because it glosses over the dilemma of politics. This dilemma consists of the fact that to paraphrase Cox [19], in theory, someone will always be a means and someone will always be an end. By glossing over this dilemma, theory bestows on morality the ideological function of justifying the power-that-be of a particular means/ends hierarchy. [20] This blurs the distinction between theory and ideology, on the one hand, and leads to the proliferation of empirical knowledge, which, having liberated itself from the dilemma of politics, in turn, leads to the proliferation of ideologies that defend the status quo of particular powers-that-be, on the other. This explains why ‘we have so many ideologies’ that are incommensurable, ‘and so few theories’ in IR pluralism today. [21] To avoid this problem, Morgenthau presented the concept of ‘interest defined as power’. As a ‘theory’ of international politics, this concept puts intellectual order on IR as a discipline. [22] An order that does not abolish pluralism, since various normative objectives lead to the proliferation of theoretical approaches in IR, but that situates these theories in the broader theoretical framework of interest defined as power and seeks to adjust those interests qua normative prioritisations of means and ends. Drawing on Morgenthau to answer the second question on demarcating the discipline and engaging in dialogue, this paper thus argues that Morgenthau’s concept of interest defined as power is a useful analytical tool here. Specifically, it argues that demarcating the discipline based on this concept opens room for engaging in dialogue in IR by leaving open the normative debate of means and ends, and thus acts as a bulwark against the proliferation of ideological camps while promoting theoretical pluralism.
This paper is in the context of the pluralism debate in IR. More precisely, the paper is situated at the intersection between two sub-debates within pluralism in IR: first, the debate on fragmentation and the end of IR, on which there was a recent special issue in the European Journal of International Relations (2013) and forum in International Relations (2017), and second in the debate on ‘dialogue’ in IR, on which special issues and forums were covered in Millennium (2011) and International Studies Review (2003). Drawing on Morgenthau, the theoretical contribution here is twofold: first, the paper illustrates the relevance of Morgenthinterest,au’s critique of social science to the contemporary debate on pluralism in IR, particularly in explaining the issue of incommensurability. Second, the paper employs Morgenthau’s concept of interest defined as power in fashion to foster dialogue in a theoretically pluralist discipline. While the normative dimension in Morgenthau, particularly his critique of social science, was highlighted by intellectual historians[23], and in various contexts.[24] And while the consequence of this critique was put forward to re-interpret the disciplinary history of IR[25], destabilize divisions between theoretical approaches [26], and provide ‘alternative theorizing’ to the meta-theoretical impasse in a fragmented discipline[27] this paper’s unique contribution lies in drawing on Morgenthau’s critique of social science to explain why theories become incommensurable ideologies, and, building on this, in offering a way forward for IR to be demarcated as a theoretically pluralist discipline where theories can find common ground for dialogue.
The argument develops as follows: first, the paper contextualizes the problem of forgetting political interests in IR pluralism—that is, the problem of political interests being used as entry points to theory but then legitimized through empirical validation and closed to normative scrutiny. Second, the paper highlights Morgenthau’s warning against this problem—that it omits the dilemma of politics — his critique of IR as a social science. Third, the paper draws on this critique to explain the issues of incommensurability and dialogue in IR pluralism. Following this, the paper concludes by drawing the implications for dialogue in IR.
IR pluralism and the problem of forgetting
This section argues that the IR pluralism debate forgets the political interests upon which the various positions stand, and thus, forfeits the adjustment of the interests these stances represent. Political interests are used as entry points to theory but then legitimized through empirical validation and closed to normative scrutiny.
To avoid reducing legitimate knowledge production in IR to one methodology, Jackson proposes a pluralism in what constitutes science. [28] As Tickner argues, however, ‘even if, following Jackson, one were to embrace a pluralist, post-foundational definition of ‘science,’ the core-periphery structure that is entrenched in Global IR (and nearly all social science) would remain untouched’.[29] This critique echoes [ earlier reviews of Jackson’s Conduct of Inquiry that problematized not only Jackson’s typology of methodological pluralism [30], and omission of ‘other-worldliness’[31], but also his underplaying of the political interests that divide these ‘methodologies’, in favor of a liberal ethos of tolerance. [32] In other words, what distinguishes methodologies is neither logic nor reason, but political interests that Jackson simply forgot. These interests are then reduced to different methodologies that retain their scholarly legitimacy through their internal, empirical validation, obscuring thus the normative basis of ‘science’. [33]
The problem of forgetting is not specific to Jackson’s Conduct of Inquiry. The latest trends in the IR pluralism debate, such as Global IR and post-colonial IR, equally suffer from the problem of forgetting. Calls for pluralism as part of Global IR aim for a diverse and inclusive IR that gives voice to ‘non-Western’ actors. [34] ‘Marked by a simultaneous increase in global and international connections and exchanges’ Katzenstein [35] argues, ‘the dialogue of Global IR will serve the purpose of articulating and reinforcing rich diversities’. ‘The idea of Global IR’, says Acharya, ‘serves as a framework for advancing IR toward a truly inclusive and universal discipline’. [36] ‘A challenge for Global IR’, therefore, is ‘how to build generalizable concepts and theories from a national or regional context that should not only apply to a specific country or region but must have broader generalization potential’.[37] But then here one may ask: who do these ‘national’ schools represent? In his critique of Acharya, Parmar [38] for example, problematizes the Global IR project where ‘the true contributions of the West and non-West are recognized, synthesized, and celebrated … and yet one in which serious problems of class inequality persist’. In forgetting class interests, Parmar’s critique highlights the particular elitist, interests the various ‘national schools’ in Global IR represent.
A corollary to Parmar’s critique here is the question of whether ‘national’ experiences in Global IR can be essentialized. Bilgin [39], for example, argues that ‘Western’ and ‘non-Western’ experiences, as well as their various interpretations, have, over the years, clashed and fused in so many ways that ‘non-Western’ ways of thinking about and doing world politics are not always devoid of ‘Western’ concepts and theories’. The central issue, however, which Bilgin does not address, is do these ‘fused’ and complex ‘West’ and ‘non-West’ even have agreed representatives. In the absence of a consensus of representatives of civilizations, a dialogue of civilizations ends up silencing voices. ‘For example’ Petito says, “the already-mentioned initiatives of Mediterranean regionalization involving European and Arab countries are to be encouraged as a way of fostering bridges of communication and mutual understanding between the European Union and the Arab League; they can also make up laboratories for the praxis of inter-civilizational dialogue.” [40]
But the Arab League does not represent ‘Arab culture’, only state representatives, largely, if not all, autocrats who suppress their people. Where is the ‘civilizational dialogue’ here? The problem with the dialogue Petito advocates is that ‘traditions’ that underlie ‘non-Western’ theories are in effect the result of political interests in over one sense: as representatives with political interests but also as representatives competing to legitimize these interests among others within each tradition. The result is that any such ‘non-Western’ theory would prioritize those who speak in the name of tradition, or the ‘local’ [41], and give the back seat to those who hold no such privilege. The ‘representatives’ of national schools, ‘traditions’, and ‘perspectives’, thus risk becoming the shadows of neorealist and neoliberal schools in the previous US experience: silencing voices, restricting IR, representing exclusionary and unadjusted political interests, escaping ‘Eurocentrism’ to introduce ‘Globacentrism’. This ‘Globacentrism’ is characterized by its forgetfulness of the political interests upon which the proliferated ‘representatives’, ‘traditions’, and ‘perspectives’ stand, and thus, the forfeit of the adjustment of the interests these stances represent. Thus, the political interests of the representatives of ‘non-Western traditions’ or the ‘local’, once used as an entry point to theory, are closed to normative scrutiny. Rather, they are pushed under theory, depoliticized, legitimized through empirical validation, and immune from normative critique.
Post-colonial scholars define pluralism in terms of ‘decolonizing’ IR. Decolonising IR is not just about ‘adding voices’, says Capan, “‘ it is not only through “adding” more critical perspectives that coloniality can be challenged but through altering the practices of said knowledge production’. [42] Thus ‘the intellectuals must firstly “decolonize their minds” and rethink the academic spaces and knowledge that they inhabit and reproduce … it is not enough to bring in new narratives or ways of conceptualizing the field, but rather the binaries and dualities upon which coloniality is premised need to be overcome’”. [43]
Here the key contribution consists of problematizing the knowledge/power relationship in Western IR and post-Western IR. Thus ‘decolonizing IR’ means exploring ‘worlding beyond the West’[44], seeking ‘alternative cosmologies’[45], and going beyond ‘epistemic imperialism’. [46] Yet, once again, post-colonialism essentializes the non-West. ‘The radical cultural relativism that such views promote as the cornerstone of pluralism and openness’ as Rosa Vasilaki forcefully argues, “ is perhaps the strongest version of essentials – the one that reaffirms stereotypes like the West as change and the Rest as stasis, Europe as modernity and the ‘global South’ as tradition, the Westerner as secular and the ‘Other’ as religious and so on – and ultimately shares the fundamentalist view that when cultures mix, a violent act against their essence is taking place.” [47]
There is not only an unproblematized acceptance of this newly established binary but of turning it into a political project whose interests are simply forgotten and hardly open to normative scrutiny. As with the Global IR project, therefore, the political interests of the representatives of the ‘rest’, ‘global South’, ‘other’, once used as an entry point to theory, are closed to normative scrutiny. Rather, normative questions are reduced to the closure of the empirical justification that theory provides within itself, relying on the grounds of the ‘culture’, ‘tradition’, etc– whatever the theorist herself finds as a legitimating tool.
In sum, the latest trends on pluralism in IR suffer from the problem of forgetting, they represent political interests but then forget these interests and forfeit their adjustment. Consequently, political interest, once used as an entry point to theory, are closed to normative scrutiny. Morgenthau warned against this problem in his critique of IR as social science because it glosses over the dilemma of politics central to IR and sought to restate the political as the adjustment of interests through his concept of ‘interest defined as power’. It is therefore to this critique that the next section turns.
Morgenthau’s critique of IR as a social science
Why is Morgenthau a suitable candidate for our analysis here? First, he was the major opponent of IR as a social science in the discipline’s history. [48] Despite Morgenthau’s opposition to IR as social science, his work has not only been misappropriated as positivist or summarised under realism but also targeted by post-colonial critics [49] for a Eurocentrism that Global IR is seeking to move beyond. Indeed, is it not the problem that IR is a ‘colonial discipline’ with ‘colonial origins’ where Morgenthau belongs? [50] Morgenthau’s work, however, does not fit into the definition(s) of ‘Eurocentrism’ in the discipline i.e. ‘a hegemonic representation and mode of knowing that claims universality for itself’. [51] To Morgenthau, there is no such thing as universality or universal history, to begin with. There are rather limits to modernity, and therefore limits of ‘modernity/coloniality’ as knowledge. [52] If the critique of Eurocentrism is also a critique of modernity, rationalism, and positivism associated with American IR, to associate this IR with Morgenthau is a mistake. Morgenthau’s career, from Scientific Man [53] onwards, consists of a critique of positivism, modernity, and rationalism. It is precise because little has been covered in this critique by Morgenthau until the end of the Cold War, that a largely caricatured understanding of his realism developed as a part of a ‘Western’ or ‘American’ IR [54], even though Morgenthau’s intellectual influences were German-speaking, for example, Freud [55], Nietzsche [56] and Weber. [57] As Hamati-Ataya [58] in earlier work on Morgenthau argues, ‘Morgenthau’s approach is successful in identifying Realism’s reflexive challenge—because it acknowledges its political nature and its relevance to scholarship’.
The second reason Morgenthau is a suitable candidate is that he shares not only a post-Nietzschean, epistemological starting point with post-colonialism but also goes beyond the latter in refusing to close normative scrutiny within the political. If decolonization, going beyond ‘Eurocentrism’, is about decolonizing the mind from binary thinking and identity formation [59], Morgenthau is an appropriate candidate to provide this critique, for he similarly critiqued Schmitt for the friend/enemy binary [60] as well as the Cartesian dualities. [61] Thus, post-colonialism and Morgenthau’s classical realism share the same epistemological starting point: post-Nietzschean perspectivism. [62] Indeed, post-colonialism, in its most radical post-structuralist critique of knowledge/power returns to the basic questions Morgenthau was grappling with in the post-Nietzschean age: ‘where to go after the provincialization of Europe, after the realization that power and knowledge are mutually constitutive and after ‘objectivity’ has been proven both false and undesirable’. [63] In both cases, there is an acknowledgment of the limits of the universalization of theory, yet in Morgenthau, there is also a refusal to close normative scrutiny within the political. [64]
What is, then, Morgenthau’s critique of IR as a social science?
Morgenthau and the critique of IR as a social science
Morgenthau’s critique of IR as a social science is two-fold. First, it is a critique of theory transcending the dilemma of politics and becoming ideology. Second, it is a critique of the proliferation of empirical knowledge, which, having liberated itself from the dilemma of politics, leads to the proliferation of ideologies that defend the status quo of particular powers that be. In an important, albeit neglected, passage, Morgenthau defines the dilemma of politics as follows: “… the totality of human actions presents itself as a hierarchy of actions each of which is the end of the preceding and a means for the following. This hierarchy culminates in the goal of all human activity, which is identical to the absolute good, be it God, humanity, the state, or the individual himself. This is the only end that is nothing but an end and hence does not serve as a means-end … In the last analysis, the doctrine that the ethical end justifies unethical means leads to the negation of absolute ethical judgments altogether. For if the ethical end justifies unethical means, the ultimate and absolute good which all human activity serves as means to an end justifies all human actions.”[65]
The dilemma here lies in the choice of a political end, which by necessity leads to the exclusion of all other ends and reduces them to ‘means’. Because of this process of exclusion, necessary choice leads to the impossibility of ‘ethical judgments altogether’. This, according to Morgenthau, leads to a basic contradiction between morality and power in matters political. But the mere presence of this contradiction does not mean that political actors surrender to the impossibility of ethical action. Rather, ‘the contradiction between the political act and morality and the logic of the power relation itself compels the political actor to make it appear as though his striving for power and the exercise of it, far from violating morality, were its consummation’. [66] the political actor engages in a process of self-deception where they portray to themselves that an act of power is an act of morality. Following this, Morgenthau argues, ‘the political actor now can proceed with a good conscience, being assured of his moral superiority and the moral inferiority of the object of his power’. [67]
The function of morality in this context is ideological: it conceals power from itself and the actor. It conceals that the truth about social science is the truth about the dilemma of means and ends. ‘That concealment, that elaborate and subtle and purposeful misunderstanding of political man and political society, is the cornerstone upon which all societies are founded’. [68] But while society confuses power with morality, and thus employs morality to play an ideological function, the role of a theory of international politics is to reveal this ‘ideological veil’, reminding power that it is power and not morality. It must remind power that it appears ‘as something other than what it is’ and that ‘deception — deception of others and self — is inseparable from the exercise of power’. [69] the role of theory here is to tell society that its morality provides an ideological cover for power that confuses power with morality. The theorist in this endeavor faces two limitations: “the limitation of origin, which determines the perspective from which he looks at society, and the limitation of purpose, which makes him wish to remain a member in good standing of that society or even to play a leading role in it.” [70]
These challenges cannot be completely met, since the perspective’s origin will always be socially and politically situated, and the theorist depends on society for their survival and reputation: “It stands to reason that political science as a social institution could never hope even to approach this ideal of a completely disinterested commitment to the truth. For no social institution can completely transcend the limitations of its origin, nor can it endeavor to free itself completely from its commitment to the society of which it forms a part, without destroying itself in the attempt.”(71]
Despite this, Morgenthau argues theory is to demonstrate an awareness of the tension between power and morality and be morally committed to the quest for the truth: “Yet while political science as a social institution cannot hope even to approach the ideal, it must be aware of its existence; and the awareness of its moral commitment to the truth must mitigate the limitations of origin and the compromises between the moral commitment and social convenience and ambition, both of which no political scientist can fully escape.” [72]
Political realism, therefore, as Morgenthau argues in his ‘fourth principle’ in Politics Among Nations, “is unwilling to gloss over and obliterate that tension [between morality and power] and thus obfuscate both the moral and the political issue by making it appear as though the stark facts of politics were morally more satisfying than they are, and the moral law less exacting than it is.” [73]
The key in the quest for truth in matters political is to reveal (and restrain) the ideological function of morality vis-à-vis power. [74] This quest is especially pressing and challenging in international politics since ‘the main function which morality performs today for international politics is ideological. It makes it appear as though the interests and policies of individual nations were the manifestations of universal moral principles’. [75] Morality does not limit power but justifies it. This blurs the distinction between morality and ideology and ideology and theory: ‘The distinction between ideology and morality becomes blurred, and so becomes the distinction between ideology and theory’. [76]
To maintain the distance between ideology and theory — that is, to render theory immune from the ideological function of morality, Morgenthau proposes his concept of ‘interest defined as power’ in a normative sense. Thus, “by making power its central concept, a theory of politics does not presume that none but power relations control political action. What it must presume is the need for a central concept that allows the observer to distinguish the field of politics from other social spheres, to orient himself [and/or herself] in the maze of empirical phenomena which make up that field, and to establish a measure of rational order within it.” [77]
Theory ‘presents a map of the political scene’ and is ‘not limited to rational explanation.’[78] Rather, ‘a theory of politics also contains a normative element’. [79] This normative element is to bring in morality not to ideologically justify power but to restrain it. [80] As Alexander Reichwein argues, therefore, to Morgenthau ‘political science in general, and any theory, in particular, was not only an instrument to explain politics but also a normative compass and an intellectual weapon’. [81]
It is in this context that Morgenthau employs the concept of ‘interests defined as power’ to demarcate IR as a discipline. He presents it as a ‘theory’ of international politics, not to present one theory among others, but to put an intellectual order on IR as a discipline. [82] This theory does not abolish pluralism, for there are diverse moral claims and normative objectives which lead to the proliferation of theoretical approaches in IR. As Morgenthau put it, ‘hypothetically one can imagine as many theories of international relations as there are legitimate intellectual perspectives from which to approach the international scene’. [83] Morgenthau was also, as he wrote in his autobiography, aware of the problem of theoretical reductionism: the ‘impossibility of accounting for complexities and varieties of political experience with the simplicities of a reductionist theory, economic [as with Marxism] or psychological [as with psychoanalysis]’. [84] Morgenthau’s ‘interest defined as power’ instead situates IR theories in a broader framework that seeks to adjust those interests qua normative prioritisations of means and ends. As Williams [85] argues, it is ‘a rhetorical device that seeks to use the political power of this concept to encourage critical reflection and dialogue about interests and their relation to identity—to how a society sees itself and wishes to be seen by others’. Morgenthau’s theory, thus as Guilhot argues, ‘emerge[s] as a normative statement on what political science should be, not as a discourse of specialization. … to delineate this territory and make it immune to the cues of behavioralism’. [86] Morgenthau’s theory stands in juxtaposition to a value-free, liberal rationalist, empirically focused, disciplined, and devoid of the dilemma of politics. ‘The focus of the theory, in the last instance, was its repudiation of a liberalism masquerading as value-free social science and rooted in the tradition of Enlightenment rationalism’. [87] This does not mean supporting value relativism, a ‘utopia power’, since Morgenthau critiques Schmitt and later Carr on this [88], but establishing the limits of what theory can achieve—the limits of both social science and power. [89] ‘A theory of politics, to be theoretically valid, must build into its theoretical structure those very qualifications which limit its theoretical validity and practical usefulness’. [90] As Hom and Steele [91] argue, therefore, ‘classical realism’s general theory of IR may be seen as a meta-argument against the possibility of a truly general theory’.
These limits include, especially, the policy-oriented theory, of which Morgenthau was highly critical.[92] The closer this theory got to power, the less it became committed to truth, particularly in Vietnam. ‘Morgenthau’s political agenda during the Vietnam War’ as Molloy[93] lately argued in this journal, thus ‘fulfills this most primary goal of a reflexive approach, i.e. a theorist’s commitment to understanding his/her role within the context of the production of knowledge and the implications of that knowledge within the social and political realms’. Morgenthau’s role as a reflexive scholar in Vietnam was to reveal the limits of power to the power-that-be, the US government. Revealing the limitations of power, however, according to Morgenthau, should not be specific to governments only—the same dynamic may also apply to any official or unofficial, male or female, top or bottom, capital or labor, or power. In exposing the limits of power, Morgenthau calls for exposing the limits of any power, of any social science, that purports to speak on behalf of any group. As Cozette [94] argues, ‘by permanently reminding Power that it lies when it pretends to embody Truth or Justice, a realist theory is a critical weapon turned against power’. Thus, pace Hamati-Ataya, perhaps the most outspoken reflexivist in IR, the ‘problem of values’ is not a problem that ‘exists only for positivism’. [95] Rather, the possibility of ‘collusion with power’ [96] extends beyond positivist research and highlights the significance of Morgenthau’s proposition that politics is about ‘interest defined as power’. For the literature, Hamati-Ataya cites as an exemplar of reflexive IR, critical theory [97], constructivism [98], and the English School [99] have not been immune from losing critical edge (e.g. see Jahn’s 1998 critique of Linklater), and/or naturalizing the political. [100]
Hamati-Ataya critiques Morgenthau’s ‘philosophical’ approach that ‘fails to unify its axiological and objectivist claims into a uniformly rigorous discourse on world affairs’.[101] What is meant here by ‘rigorous discourse’? If the meaning here is empirically verifiable statements a la positivism, then Morgenthau rejects such discourse because of the complexity of social planning.[102] Moreover, it is in this movement to ‘rigor’ that reflexivist IR loses its reflection and becomes forgetful of its political origins. This is not only clear above with the literature that Hamati-Ataya associates reflexivism[103], but also a more general critique raised against reflexivist research in IR that turns from ‘a project based on recognizing one’s limitations . . . into a claim to enlightenment’.[104] Contra this scholarship, as Molloy argues in response to Hamati-Ataya, Morgenthau’s realism is ‘politically reflexive regarding scholarship and its relationship to power and the modes of knowledge production’. [105] Politically reflexive because it is reflexive with a political agenda: a responsibility to challenge the powers-that-be through invoking a normative concept of power as a bulwark against morality playing an ideological function of justifying, rather than exposing the limitations of, power. [106]
The necessity of Morgenthau’s normative meaning of power lies in the political dilemma underlying IR or social science. When IR as social science glosses over this dilemma, it offers not only one normative judgment of the means and ends in the hierarchy of values, but also turns theory into an ideology that switches the function of morality from the restraint of power to the justification of a particular power-that-be. This leads to the proliferation of empirical, causal knowledge, which, having liberated itself from the dilemma of politics, proliferates political ideologies that protect the status quo of particular powers that be. This explains why, to Morgenthau, a focus on causality or causal analysis separated from the political dilemmas in action gives an inadequate concept of science. Indeed, in Science: Servant or Master, Morgenthau associates the latter conception of science with the ancient, immanent, Aristotelian, concept, which he juxtaposes with the modern concept: “Aristotle was satisfied with the immanent meaning of science. Here science finds its meaning within itself, in the theoretical constitution of the human soul that aspires to knowledge for its own sake … Modern consciousness revolts against this indifference … We are no longer capable of that self-assurance, which appears naïve in retrospect, that salutes each new knowledge as a new victory carrying its justification within itself.” [107]
Morgenthau’s critique of IR as a social science is thus that, by transcending the dilemma of politics, it first turns theory into ideology. And second, it leads to the proliferation of empirical knowledge, internally validated and yet inadequate, as it serves as the ideological justification of the status quo of particular powers-that-be. Morgenthau’s ‘realism is, therefore’, as Cozette argues, ‘best described as a permanent critique of the powers-that-be that constantly challenges the status quo and the ideological apparatus upon which it rests’. [108] The significance of this Morgenthauian critique is that it helps illuminate the issues of incommensurability and dialogue in IR pluralism, to which the paper now turns.
Morgenthau, incommensurability and dialogue in IR pluralism
This section firstly argues that Morgenthau’s critique of IR as social science can explain why IR theories today are incommensurable and cannot engage in dialogue. By transcending the dilemma of politics, as highlighted by Morgenthau, theories today are ideological camps that bestow on morality an ideological function that justifies their powers-that-be that serve particular means/ends hierarchies. This leads to the proliferation of empirical causal analyses that cannot be debated since they rely on these hierarchies that theory ideologically justifies and offers internal validation. Building on this, the section secondly argues that the central task to engage in dialogue without glossing over pluralism in IR is to start with the political in a Morgenthauian sense: to demarcate the discipline based on the concept of interest defined in terms of power.
With notable exceptions [109], IR scholars often draw on Kuhn’s definition of incommensurability. [110] This is problematic since the limitation in social science pertains not only to the inapplicability of the methods of natural science to social science. Rather, it is that many of the themes in the philosophy of science, such as Kuhn’s ‘incommensurability’, change their meaning once they traverse the realm of the natural to the social. They add to the empirical problem the dilemma of politics. The addition of this dilemma in social science means that theoretical camps are chained on a springboard of means and ends that render theories ‘incommensurable’ which differs from Kuhn’s understanding of the term. [111] For it is the political positions that these theoretical arguments hold that make them exclusionary of one another. This means the question of incommensurability and its link to the fragmentation of the discipline is not simply one of diverse ‘perspectives’ [112], or ‘methodologies’. [113] And nor does it simply lie in the ‘complexity of society’ per se [114], or a misunderstanding of epistemology. [115] It is, rather, as Jahn argues, ‘the modern episteme that endows the individual elements of such complex systems with their internal nature and hence leads to fragmentation’. [116] As with Morgenthau, however, the key here is not to surrender to a ubiquitous science that is merely justified through internal, empirical, validation.
The ubiquity of this science was highlighted in Kurki’s analysis of causality [117], which draws on Aristotle to highlight various causalities across the positivist-post-positivist spectrum. But IR as a discipline cannot justify each theoretical contribution considering its empirical, causal validation. It cannot accept each new voice as a ‘victory in itself’. [118] Since then, the normative underpinnings of causal decisions are closed to scrutiny and each victory becomes part of an ideological camp that bestows on morality the ideological function of justifying the power-that-be of particular means/ends hierarchies. By concerning itself with ‘scientific ontology’ i.e. debate over theoretical explanation, rather than what explanation is [119], IR obscures the normative basis of ‘science’ [120], which entails the prioritization of means and ends Morgenthau highlighted. Each ‘victory’ becomes part of an ideological camp, whose imposition of particular means/ends hierarchies as an act of power cannot be restrained by morality but bestows on morality the ideological function of justifying such hierarchies. Here, the empirical causal analysis proliferates not only but also cannot be debated, since it relies on normative hierarchies that theory ideologically justifies and offers empirical, causal validation. This does not, per se, indicate a ‘healthy and dynamic discipline’ [121], particularly when fragmentation may mean a lack of a normative dialogue between the various ideological ‘camps’. [122]
Of course, not all scholars agree that the incommensurability of isms is intrinsic to the subject of politics. Lake [123], for example, finds the evil in the ‘isms’ themselves, the ‘pathologies’ of grand theories, that can be escaped in mid-level theorizing. This view is shared by those who call for more eclectic hypothesis testing[124], more focus on concrete political problems [125], and ‘causal mechanisms’. [126] But these calls, as Jahn noted, ‘rest on meta-theoretical commitments and methodological practices from which [they] receive [their] scientific status and validation’. [127] For example, the focus on causality and ‘causal mechanisms’ in eclectic and mid-range theory has been associated by some with scientific realism [128], and by others with neo-positivism. [129] Once this commitment is taken as a given, there is a shift from theory to methods. One issue with such a shift, as Mearsheimer and Walt [130] argued, is that different (meta)-theoretical perspectives might lead to different empirical conclusions. These conclusions are not simply based on different interpretations of causality but represent political interests that are in turn linked to the meta-theoretical commitments [131], which mid-range theory and analytical eclecticism take as a given. These political interests bestow on morality the ideological function of legitimizing the normative hierarchies of the particular powers-that-be that mid-range theory and analytical eclecticism serve. This can be contrasted with ‘grand theories’, which as Felix Berenskötter argues, possess an ‘ability to ground their ontologies, explanations, and prescriptions in answers to philosophical questions of what drives ‘us’, where and who ‘we’ are, and should be, in space and time. As the answers can only ever be particular, they are also political’. [132] Thus Berenskötter suggests ‘deep theorizing’ as ‘also a form of political theorizing’. [133] In this context, ‘causality’ cannot present the normative evaluation required of these ‘deep theories’, since causality itself is built on the choice of normative means and ends central to politics. The key task to engage in dialogue without glossing over pluralism in this context becomes to start with the political in a Morgenthauian sense: to demarcate the discipline based on the concept of interest defined in terms of power and begin with a normative debate regarding means and ends.
Morgenthau’s political and dialogue in IR pluralism
Calls for dialogue in IR are not new [134], and, like pluralism, dialogue has over one meaning. Previous attempts to address the question of dialogue in IR presented ‘via media’ and/or ‘middle grounds’. Yet, remaining within the rationalist end of the methodological spectrum, these attempts were at best contentious, at worst, feeding into the latter’s exclusionary dominance in IR. As Steve Smith argued of mainstream constructivism for example: “The main debates in the discipline for the next decade will be between rationalism and constructivism, but this is a little misleading because it implies that constructivism is positioned between the two approaches: I think that some of the most cited authors are not at all positioned between the two, but are part of rationalism.” [135]
Recent calls for dialogue in IR have thus been, rightly, suspicious of such attempts at ‘grand theorizing’. Dunne et al. [136] instead called for ‘integrative pluralism’, which ‘allows for more diversity than ‘unity through pluralism’ and more interaction than ‘dis-engaged pluralism’. ‘Integrative pluralism’, thus, ‘is not an attempt to forge competing knowledge claims into one overarching position that subsumes them all. It is not a form of theoretical synthesis, nor is it a middle ground that eclectically claims to take the best of various theories to forge them into a ‘grand theory of everything. [137] Rather, ‘the ultimate test of integrative pluralism will be researchers from multiple perspectives engaging in the practice of pluralism through engagement with alternative positions where their concerns and research interests overlap’. [138] Others, such as Hutchings, call for ‘dissonance’ and ‘negotiation’ as key ethical concepts for dialogue in ‘pluriversality’. [139] Calls to transcend the essentialism of the ‘non-West’, turn to dialogue via redefining the universal in terms of egalitarian principles [140], and/or heterogeneity. [141]
These contributions raise an important question: on what basis can scholars ‘engage’ in dialogue or ‘negotiate’ an ‘egalitarian’ or ‘non-hegemonic’ universality here? Here, the normative dimension is downgraded in the literature on dialogue in IR pluralism: there is no mention of political interests—instead, ‘theoretical results’ that need to be explicit. [142] The success of ‘negotiation… involves cultivating relational and creative resources for finding ways of working with others’. [143] Transcending the essentializing of the ‘non-West’ means drawing on theoretical schemes, such as ‘uneven and combined development’. [144] But if theories are ideological camps, as highlighted by Morgenthau above, then making theoretical results explicit or being negotiable is not sufficient to engage in dialogue as part of a pluralist discipline. This is because theories remain internally validated, and given the omission of the dilemma of politics, they do not challenge but justify their powers-that-be that serve particular means/ends hierarchies. Therefore, as Jackson argued, theoretical schemes such as ‘uneven and combined development’ take IR ‘out of one [ideological] prison, into another’. [145]
Given this background, one cannot, like Jackson [146], simply jump into ‘dialogue’ with a liberal ethos and expect it to perform the political task of accommodation. Pace Habermas, power cannot be substituted for the rationality of the ‘better argument’. [147] And nor can dialogue mean ‘reciprocal exchange for mutual learning’ [148], without first accounting for how such learning can take place when the hierarchies of means and ends contradict, and mutually exclude, one another. Dialogue is an imprecise term, not only in the sense of what kind of dialogue are we having and the boundaries/rules of dialogue [149] but also in what structural and ideological conditions are necessary as a prerequisite for dialogue. If dialogue is to retain its meaning in the Greek term dia-logos, which ‘is best understood as an effort by two or more people to make something new together’ [150], therefore, the central task to avoid the ‘evil of isms’ is to start with the political in a Morgenthauian sense: to begin with a normative debate regarding means and ends, and thus, to ‘raise the question of the meaning of knowledge itself and to answer it by searching not for the knowledge of any kind, but for the knowledge that is worth knowing’. [151]
Critics may object here: ‘and who will decide’ what ‘knowledge’ is ‘worth knowing’? Should we not, given we have no answer to this question, then agree to keep ‘IR’ as broad/pluralist as possible? [152] The problem with such objections is that despite their call for pluralism, they set—often liberal—normative boundaries to the scientific debate and do not open these boundaries to debate. [153] They settle the normative debate before the discussion starts and thus close the discussion of normative justifications. An alternative approach here is for theory to be reflexive about the trade-offs involved in theory building — of the theory’s means and ends. And second, for theory to be open to engaging in a dialogue over these trade-offs. This way, theory can not only be reflexive and open to dialogue but also pursue a normative concept of power a la Morgenthau, as opposed to an empirical concept of power a la Schmitt. [154] The benefit of this concept is that it opens room for engaging in dialogue in IR by leaving open the normative debate of means and ends and thus acts as a bulwark against the proliferation of ideological camps while promoting theoretical pluralism. The concluding section of the paper illustrates this benefit by drawing the implications of Morgenthau’s critique of social science for dialogue in the IR pluralism debate.
Conclusion: ‘interest defined as power’ for dialogue in IR pluralism
Morgenthau’s skepticism about social science as the instrument of power-that-be has waned over the decades. As Michael Williams argued in his contribution to the 2013 special issue on the ‘end of IR’ in this journal: “IR lost its previous skepticism toward social ‘science’ and became a standard-bearer for precisely the kinds of political knowledge that [classical realists] had been at pains to reject and which they sought to construct the field of IR in opposition toward. Indeed, if one wished to be provocative, it is possible to say that from this perspective, what is often taken as the defining moment in the invention of IR theory — the publication of Kenneth Waltz’s Theory of International Politics — actually marked the culmination of a move away from the field’s beginnings and represents the ‘end’ of IR theory as conceived by [classical realists].” [155]
Building on this, this paper drew on Morgenthau’s critique of IR as a social science to argue that it can explain the proliferation of camps in IR that are incommensurable and cannot engage in dialogue. By transcending the dilemma of politics, as highlighted by Morgenthau, theories today are ideological camps that give morality an ideological function that justifies their powers-that-be that serve particular means/ends hierarchies. This leads to the proliferation of empirical causal analyses that cannot be debated since they rely on political interests that theory ideologically justifies and offers internal validation. To avoid this problem, the paper proposed demarcating the discipline through Morgenthau’s concept of ‘interest defined as power’. This concept, the paper argued, opens room for engaging in dialogue in IR by leaving open the normative debate of means and ends, and thus acts as a bulwark against the proliferation of ideological camps, without glossing over theoretical pluralism. This raises the question: how can theory pursue a normative concept of power a la Morgenthau—a concept of power whose purpose is not to impose, but to mutually adjust the various interests in the political? To illustrate the benefit of this concept, the concluding section of the paper depicts its implications for dialogue by drawing on two examples from the IR pluralism literature cited at the outset.
The first example is Jackson’s Conduct of Inquiry. In his reply to Jackson’s Conduct of Inquiry, Suganami argues that the choice of different methodologies depends on the type of questions the researcher asks. [156] Suganami argues that this choice is determined by ‘politics’. This politics determines whether the researcher seeks (neo)positivist or analytical approaches to control the status quo or to transform the status quo into a more emancipatory order with critical realism and reflexivism. [157] The lesson this paper draws from Morgenthau here is that whatever the choice is, the intrusion of politics Suganami highlights means that the theorist has a responsibility to acknowledge the limitations of the power-that-be of both the status quo and the emancipatory order by allowing normative scrutiny to the ends and means of theory. For example, if the theorist seeks to control and predict within the parameters of the status quo [158], it is crucial in this case not to remove the theorist as a decision-maker and justify this status quo through the ‘rational’ imperatives of some ‘system level’ abstraction. [159] For this will allow foreign policy elites ‘to define political rationality in their interest and to protect those interests as some objective raison d’état’. [160] And this means as Behr and Heath [161] warned, that Morgenthau’s realism will lose its original role as an ideology critique, and (neo)-realism will end up ideologically justifying the foreign policy apparatus that serves some elite-based interest. To overcome this issue of theory becoming the ideology of the status quo, therefore, it is crucial to identify, first, who this status quo serves as an end and who is excluded as a means, and second, why this ends/means hierarchy is justified. The choice of means and ends can then open a dialogue with other theories that seek to overthrow this status quo for an order that produces new hierarchies of means and ends. It is noteworthy here that IR theorists, particularly post-positivists, already do this in their critique of other theories (especially positivists). For example, contra calls for a pluralist IR with ‘policy relevance’ [162], feminists problematize the reduction of relevance to the realm of security narrowly defined in terms of the foreign policy elites as an end. [163] This critique should not only be applied to theories branded as ‘elitist’ or ‘positivist’ but to all theories, including the various strands of feminism. Once all theories are open to normative scrutiny in this same manner, a normative concept of power can then play its function of mutually adjusting the various political interests the various hierarchies of means and ends represent, and, crucially, act as a bulwark against ideological camps without glossing over theoretical pluralism.
The second example from the literature cited at the outset of the paper is the Global IR project associated with Acharya and Buzan’s works. [164] Here, calls to include Brasilian [165], Chinese [166], Indian [167], Japanese [168], and Turkish [169] schools in IR, cannot evade the question of who are the ends and means of these schools without being exclusionary [170] and thus bestowing on morality what Morgenthau referred to as the ideological function of justifying power. Here ‘national schools of IR might [not only] become, or be seen to become, tools of government in the service of the national interest’, as Buzan once raised his concern [171] but also have no bulwark against the ideological justification of such interest in case it purports to represent universal moral values. Thus, in Global IR, Morgenthau’s ‘interest defined as power’ stands as a bulwark against the danger of ‘national schools’ beyond the West ‘trying to replicate the Western success of universalizing their history and political theory’. [172] The normative meaning the concept of power holds here means to adjust the various interests between and within these schools. [173] It means refusing to depoliticize the theory’s political stance, which leads to the theory transcending the dilemma in politics and thus turning into ideology. It means heeding Morgenthau’s warning in Politics Among Nations that ‘all nations are tempted… to clothe their particular aspirations and actions in moral purposes of the universe’ and ‘it is exactly the concept of interest defined in terms of power that saves us from both that moral excess and that political folly’. [174] This warning is especially relevant today with the rise of excessive nationalism in world politics, and in particular in the East Asia context. [175] Morgenthau’s lesson to the Global IR project, therefore, is not to universalize the particular (as Acharya advocates), but to put a check on the powers-that-be that these schools represent by opening to normative scrutiny the means and ends of their ethical hierarchies within as well as between nations.
[1] Jackson, P (2011) The Conduct of Inquiry in International Relations: Philosophy of Science and Its Implications for the Study of World Politics. London: Routledge. Google Scholar
[2] Acharya, A (2014) Global international relations (IR) and regional worlds. International Studies Quarterly 58(4): 647–659. Google Scholar | Crossref | ISI
[3] Sil, R, Katzenstein, P (2008) Eclectic theorizing in the study and practice of international relations. In: Reus-Smit, C, Snidal, D (eds) The Oxford Handbook of International Relations. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Google Scholar
[4] Tickner, A (2016) Knowledge is power: challenging IR’s Eurocentric narrative. International Studies Review 18(1): 157–159. Google Scholar | Crossref
[5] Brown, C (2013) The poverty of grand theory. European Journal of International Relations 19(3): 483–497. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[6] Bennett, A (2013) The mother of all isms: causal mechanisms and structured pluralism in international relations theory. European Journal of International Relations 19(3): 459–481. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[7] Mearsheimer, J, Walt, S (2013) Leaving theory behind: why simplistic hypothesis testing is bad for international relations. European Journal of International Relations 19(3): 427–57. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals
[8] Grovogui, S (2006) Mind, body, and gut! elements of a postcolonial human rights discourse. In: Jones, BG (ed.) Decolonizing International Relations. Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield, 179–196. Google Scholar
[9] Jones, G (2006) Introduction: international relations, Eurocentrism, and Imperialism. In: Jones, G (ed.) Decolonizing International Relations. Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield, 1–19. Google Scholar
[10] Sylvester, C (2013) Experiencing the end and afterlives of international relations/Theory. European Journal of International Relations 19(3): 609–626. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[11] Rosenberg, J (2016) International relations in the prison of political science. International Relations 30(2): 127–153. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[12] Blaney, D, Tickner, A (2017a) International relations in the prison of colonial modernity. International Relations 31(1): 71–75. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[13] Jackson, P (2017) Out of one prison, into another? Comments on Rosenberg. International Relations 31(1): 81–84. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals
[14] Sears, N (2018) Multiplicity – within and between. International Relations 32(2): 242–243. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[15] Corry, O (2018) Societies are not the only source of multiplicity. International Relations 32(2): 243–245. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[16] Peltonen, H (2018) A prison break into the past? A comment on Justin Rosenberg’s IR in the prison of political science. International Relations 32(2): 245–246. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[17] Powel, B (2018) Deepening ‘multiplicity’: a response to Rosenberg. International Relations 32(2): 248–250. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[18] Lake, D (2016) White man’s IR: an intellectual confession. Perspectives on Politics 14(4): 1112–1122. Google Scholar | Crossref
[19] Cox, R (1981) Social forces, states, and world orders: beyond international relations theory. Millennium 10(2): 126–155. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals
[20] The notion of ‘powers-that-be’ is employed in this paper in a broad sense to include any position of power, since, from a Morgenthauian perspective, all positions are interested, including (e.g. reflexivist) positions whose aim is to expose the interests of others.
[21] Morgenthau, H (1959) The nature and limits of a theory of international relations. In: Fox, WTR (ed.) Theoretical Aspects of International Relations. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. Google Scholar
[22] Guilhot, N (ed.) (2011) The Invention of International Relations Theory. New York: Columbia University Press. Google Scholar
Guzzini, S (1998) Realism in International Relations and International Political Economy. London: Routledge. Google Scholar
[23] Frei, C (2002) Hans J. Morgenthau: An Intellectual Biography. Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press. Google Scholar
Guilhot, N (ed.) (2011) The Invention of International Relations Theory. New York: Columbia University Press. Google Scholar
Petersen, U (1999) Breathing Nietzsche’s air: new reflections on Morgenthau’s concepts of power and human nature. Alternatives 24(1): 83–118. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[24] Karkour, H (2018) Unipolarity’s unpeacefulness and US foreign policy: consequences of a coherent system of irrationality. International Relations 32(1): 60–79. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
Molloy, S (2009) Aristotle, Epicurus, Morgenthau and the political ethics of the lesser evil. Journal of International Political Theory 5(1): 94–112. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals
Roesch, F (2014) Pouvoir, puissance, and politics: Hans Morgenthau’s dualistic concept of power? Review of International Studies 40(2): 349–365. Google Scholar | Crossref
[25] Williams, M (2013) In the beginning: the international relations enlightenment and the ends of international relations theory. European Journal of International Relations 19(3): 647–665. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[26] Behr, H, Roesch, F (2012) Introduction. In: Behr, H, Roesch, F (eds) The Concept of the Political (trans. Vidal, M). Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. Google Scholar
Behr, H, Williams, M (2017) Interlocuting classical realism and critical theory: negotiating ‘divides’ in international relations theory. Journal of International Political Theory 13(1): 3–17. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[27] Paipais, V (2014) Between politics and the political: reading Hans J. Morgenthau’s double critique of depoliticization. Millennium 42(2): 354–75. Google Scholar
[28] Jackson, P (2011) The Conduct of Inquiry in International Relations: Philosophy of Science and Its Implications for the Study of World Politics. London: Routledge. Google Scholar
Jackson, P (2017) Out of one prison, into another? Comments on Rosenberg. International Relations 31(1): 81–84. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals
[29] Tickner, A (2013) Core, periphery and (neo)imperialist international relations. European Journal of International Relations 19(3): 627–646. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[30] Humphreys, A (2013) Applying Jackson’s methodological ideal-types: problems of differentiation and classification. Millennium 41(2): 290–308. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
Wight, C (2013) The dualistic grounding of monism: science, pluralism and typological truncation. Millennium 41(2): 326–345. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[31] Acharya, A (2011) Dialogue and discovery: in search of international relations theories beyond the West. Millennium 39(3): 619–637. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[32] Suganami, H (2013) Meta-Jackson: rethinking Patrick Thaddeus Jackson’s conduct of inquiry. Millennium 41(2): 248–269. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[33] Reus-Smit, C (2013) Beyond Metatheory? European Journal of International Relations 19(3): 589–608. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[34] Acharya, A, Buzan, B (2019) The Making of Global International Relations: Origins and Evolution of IR at its Centenary. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Google Scholar | Crossref
Gelardi, M (2019) Moving global IR forward – a road map. International Studies Review 1–23. Epub ahead of print 3 October 2019. DOI: 10.1093/isr/viz049 Google Scholar | Crossref
[35] Katzenstein, P (2016) Diversity and empathy. International Studies Review 18(1): 151–153. Google Scholar | Crossref
[36] Acharya, A (2016) Advancing global IR: challenges, contentions, and contributions. International Studies Review 18(1): 5. Google Scholar | Crossref
[37] Id. p. 6
[38] Parmar, I (2019) Global power shifts, diversity, and hierarchy in international politics. Ethics and International Affairs 33(2): 231–244. Google Scholar | Crossref
[39] Bilgin, P (2008) Thinking past ‘Western’ IR? Third World Quarterly 29(1): 5–23. Google Scholar | Crossref | ISI
[40] Petito, F (2016) Dialogue of civilizations in a multipolar world: toward a multicivilizational- multiplex world order. International Studies Review 18(1): 78–91. Google Scholar | Crossref | ISI
[41] Gelardi, M (2019) Moving global IR forward – a road map. International Studies Review 1–23. Epub ahead of print 3 October 2019. DOI: 10.1093/isr/viz049 Google Scholar | Crossref
[42] Capan, ZG (2017) Decolonising international relations? Third World Quarterly 38(1): 1–15. Google Scholar | Crossref
[43] Id.
Blaney, D, Tickner, A (2017b) Worlding, ontological politics and the possibility of a decolonial IR. Millennium 45(3): 293–311. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
Fonseca, M (2019) Global IR and western dominance: moving forward or Eurocentric entrapment? Millennium 48(1): 45–59. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
Holden, G (2014) Worlding beyond the West. Cooperation and Conflict 49(1): 133–140. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
Sabaratnam, M (2011) IR in dialogue. But can we change the subjects? A typology of decolonising strategies for the study of world politics. Millennium 39(3): 781–803. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
Zondi, S (2018) Decolonising international relations and its theory: a critical conceptual meditation. Politikon 45(1): 16–31. Google Scholar | Crossref
[44] Holden, G (2014) Worlding beyond the West. Cooperation and Conflict 49(1): 133–140. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[45] Blaney, D, Tickner, A (2017b) Worlding, ontological politics and the possibility of a decolonial IR. Millennium 45(3): 293–311. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[46] Zondi, S (2018) Decolonising international relations and its theory: a critical conceptual meditation. Politikon 45(1): 16–31. Google Scholar | Crossref
[47] Vasilaki, R (2012) Provincialising IR? deadlocks and prospects in post-Western IR theory. Millennium 41(1): 3–22. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[48] Guilhot, N (ed.) (2011) The Invention of International Relations Theory. New York: Columbia University Press. Google Scholar
Williams, M (2013) In the beginning: the international relations enlightenment and the ends of international relations theory. European Journal of International Relations 19(3): 647–665. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[49] Hobson, J (2012) The Eurocentric Conception of World Politics: Western International Theory,1760–2010. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Google Scholar | Crossref
Berenskötter, F (2018) Deep theorizing in international relations. European Journal of International Relations 24(4): 814–840. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[50] Capan, ZG (2017) Decolonising international relations? Third World Quarterly 38(1): 1–15. Google Scholar | Crossref
[51] Escobar, A (2004) Beyond the third world: imperial globality, global coloniality, and anti-globalization social movements. Third World Quarterly 25(1): 207–230. Google Scholar | Crossref | ISI
[52] Capan, ZG (2017) Decolonising international relations? Third World Quarterly 38(1): 1–15. Google Scholar | Crossref
[53] Morgenthau, H (1946) Scientific Man Versus Power Politics. Chicago: Phoenix. Google Scholar
[54] (Behr and Heath, 2009)
[55] Schuett, R (2010) Political Realism, Freud and Human Nature in International Relations. New York: Palgrave Macmillan. Google Scholar | Crossref
[56] Frei, C (2002) Hans J. Morgenthau: An Intellectual Biography. Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press. Google Scholar
[57] Turner, S, Mazur, G (2009) Morgenthau as a Weberian methodologist. European Journal of International Relations 15(3): 477–504. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[58] Hamati-Ataya, I (2010) Knowing and judging in international relations theory: realism and the reflexive challenge. Review of International Studies 36(4): 1079–1101. Google Scholar | Crossref | ISI
[59] Capan, ZG (2017) Decolonising international relations? Third World Quarterly 38(1): 1–15. Google Scholar | Crossref
[60] Roesch, F (2014) Pouvoir, puissance, and politics: Hans Morgenthau’s dualistic concept of power? Review of International Studies 40(2): 349–365. Google Scholar | Crossref
[61] Behr, H (2013) Security, politics and public discourse: a Morgenthauian approach. In: Bevir, M, Daddow, O, Hall, I (eds) Interpreting Global Security. London: Routledge. Google Scholar
[62] Vasilaki, R (2012) Provincialising IR? deadlocks and prospects in post-Western IR theory. Millennium 41(1): 3–22. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[63] Id.
[64] Paipais, V (2014) Between politics and the political: reading Hans J. Morgenthau’s double critique of depoliticisation. Millennium 42(2): 354–75. Google Scholar
[65] Morgenthau, H (1945) The evil of politics and ethics of evil. Ethics 56(1): 9. Google Scholar | Crossref | ISI
[66] Morgenthau, H (1962a) Politics in the Twentieth Century: Vol.1 the Decline of Democratic Politics. p. 13. Chicago: Chicago University Press. Google Scholar
[67] Id.
[68] Morgenthau, H (1958) Dilemmas of Politics, p.28. Chicago: Chicago University Press. Google Scholar
[69] Morgenthau, H (1970) Truth and Power: Essays of a Decade 1960–1970, p. 14. New York: Praeger. Google Scholar
[70] Morgenthau, H (1959) The nature and limits of a theory of international relations. In: Fox, WTR (ed.) Theoretical Aspects of International Relations. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. Google Scholar
[71] Id., p. 22.
[72] Id., p. 23.
[73] Morgenthau, H (1978) Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, 5th edn. New York: Alfred Knopf. Google Scholar
[74] Morgenthau, H (1959) The nature and limits of a theory of international relations. In: Fox, WTR (ed.) Theoretical Aspects of International Relations. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. Google Scholar
[75] Id., p. 28.
[76] Morgenthau, H (1959) The nature and limits of a theory of international relations. In: Fox, WTR (ed.) Theoretical Aspects of International Relations. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. Google Scholar
[77] Morgenthau, H (1958) Dilemmas of Politics. Chicago: Chicago University Press. Google Scholar
[78] Id., p. 40.
[79] Id.
[80] Lebow, N (2011) German Jews and American realism. Constellations 18(4): 545–566. Google Scholar | Crossref
[81] Reichwein, A (2016) The responsibility of the intellectuals in times of political crisis. Available at: http://medandreord.dk/the-responsibility-of-the-intellectuals-in-times-of-political-crisis/ (accessed 1 December 2019). Google Scholar
[82] Guilhot, N (ed.) (2011) The Invention of International Relations Theory. New York: Columbia University Press. Google Scholar
Guilhot, N (ed.) (2011) The Invention of International Relations Theory. New York: Columbia University Press. Google Scholar
[83] Morgenthau, H (1959) The nature and limits of a theory of international relations. In: Fox, WTR (ed.) Theoretical Aspects of International Relations. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. Google Scholar
[84] Morgenthau, H (1977) An intellectual autobiography. In: Kenneth, T, Robert, M. (eds) A Tribute to Hans J. Morgenthau. Washington, DC: New Republic. Google Scholar
[85] Williams, M (2005) The Realist Tradition and the Limits of International Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Google Scholar | Crossref
[86] Guilhot, N (ed.) (2011) The Invention of International Relations Theory. New York: Columbia University Press. Google Scholar
[87] Id.
[88] Morgenthau, H (1948) The political science of E. H. Carr. World Politics 1(1): 127–134. Google Scholar | Crossref | ISI
Morgenthau, H (1948) The political science of E. H. Carr. World Politics 1(1): 127–134. Google Scholar | Crossref | ISI
[89] Behr, H (2013) Security, politics and public discourse: a Morgenthauian approach. In: Bevir, M, Daddow, O, Hall, I (eds) Interpreting Global Security. London: Routledge. Google Scholar
[90] Morgenthau, H (1959) The nature and limits of a theory of international relations. In: Fox, WTR (ed.) Theoretical Aspects of International Relations. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. Google Scholar
[91] Hom, A, Steele, B (2010) Open horizons: the temporal visions of reflexive realism. International Studies Review 12(2): 271–300. Google Scholar | Crossref | ISI
[92] Wallace, W (1996) Truth and power, monks and technocrats: theory and practice in international relations. Review of International Studies 22(3): 301–321. Google Scholar | Crossref
Desch, M (2015) Technique trumps relevance: the professionalization of political science and the marginalization of security studies. Perspectives on Politics 13(2): 377–393. Google Scholar | Crossref
[93] Molloy, S (2019) Realism and reflexivity: Morgenthau, academic freedom and dissent. European Journal of International Relations. Epub ahead of print 14 August 2019. DOI: 10.1177/1354066119868283 Google Scholar | SAGE Journals
[94] Cozette, M (2008) Reclaiming the critical dimension of realism: Hans J. Morgenthau on the ethics of scholarship. Review of International Studies 34(1): 5–27. Google Scholar | Crossref | ISI
[95] Hamati-Ataya, I (2011) The “Problem of Values” and international relations scholarship: from applied reflexivity to Reflexivism. International Studies Review 13(2): 259–287. Google Scholar | Crossref | ISI
Sjoberg, L (2015) Locating relevance in security studies. Perspectives on Politics 13(2): 396–398. Google Scholar | Crossref
[96] Hamati-Ataya, I (2011) The “Problem of Values” and international relations scholarship: from applied reflexivity to Reflexivism. International Studies Review 13(2): 259–287. Google Scholar | Crossref | ISI
[97] Linklater, A (1992) The question of the next stage in international relations theory: a critical-theoretical point of view. Millennium 21(1): 77–98. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[98] Onuf, N (1989) World of Our Making. Oxford and New York: Routledge. Google Scholar
[99] Dunne, T (1998) Inventing International Society: A History of the English School. Basingstoke: Macmillan Press. Google Scholar | Crossref
[100] Epstein, C (2013) Constructivism or the eternal return of universals in international relations. Why returning to language is vital to prolonging the owl’s flight. European Journal of International Relations 19(3): 499–519. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[101] Hamati-Ataya, I (2010) Knowing and judging in international relations theory: realism and the reflexive challenge. Review of International Studies 36(4): 1079–1101. Google Scholar | Crossref | ISI
[102] Morgenthau, H (1944) The limitations of science and the problem of social planning. Ethics 54(3): 174–185. Google Scholar | Crossref
[103] Hamati-Ataya, I (2011) The “Problem of Values” and international relations scholarship: from applied reflexivity to Reflexivism. International Studies Review 13(2): 259–287. Google Scholar | Crossref | ISI
[104] Knafo, S (2016) Bourdieu and the dead end of reflexivity: on the impossible task of locating the subject. Review of International Studies 42(1): 25–47. Google Scholar | Crossref | ISI
[105] Molloy, S (2019) Realism and reflexivity: Morgenthau, academic freedom and dissent. European Journal of International Relations. Epub ahead of print 14 August 2019. DOI: 10.1177/1354066119868283 Google Scholar | SAGE Journals
[106] Behr, H, Roesch, F (2012) Introduction. In: Behr, H, Roesch, F (eds) The Concept of the Political (trans. Vidal, M ). Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. Google Scholar
[107] Morgenthau, H (1972) Science: Servant or Master? New York: New American Library. Google Scholar
[108] Cozette, M (2008) Reclaiming the critical dimension of realism: Hans J. Morgenthau on the ethics of scholarship. Review of International Studies 34(1): 5–27. Google Scholar | Crossref | ISI
[109] Wight, C (1996) Incommensurability and cross paradigm communication in international relations theory: what’s the frequency Kenneth? Millennium 25(2): 291–319. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[110] Hollis and Smith, 1990
Lapid, J (1989) The third debate: on the prospects of international theory in a post-positivist era. International Studies Quarterly 33(3): 235–254. Google Scholar | Crossref | ISI
Monteiro, N, Ruby, K (2009) IR and the false promise of philosophical foundations. International Theory 1(1): 15–48. Google Scholar | Crossref | ISI
Vasquez, J (1997) The realist paradigm and degenerative versus progressive research programs: an appraisal of neotraditional research on Waltz’s balancing proposition. American Political Science Review 91(4): 899–912. Google Scholar | Crossref | ISI
[111] Kuhn, T (1970) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: Chicago University Press. Google Scholar
[112] Wight, C (1996) Incommensurability and cross paradigm communication in international relations theory: what’s the frequency Kenneth? Millennium 25(2): 291–319. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[113] Jackson, P (2011) The Conduct of Inquiry in International Relations: Philosophy of Science and Its Implications for the Study of World Politics. London: Routledge. Google Scholar
[114] Dunne, T, Hansen, L, Wight, C (2013) The end of international relations theory? European Journal of International Relations 19(3): 405–425. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
Jahn, B (2017) Theorizing the political relevance of international relations theory. International Studies Quarterly 61(1): 64–77. Google Scholar
[115] Wight, C (2013) The dualistic grounding of monism: science, pluralism and typological truncation. Millennium 41(2): 326–345. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[116] Jahn, B (2017) Theorizing the political relevance of international relations theory. International Studies Quarterly 61(1): 64–77. Google Scholar
[117] Kurki, M (2006) Causes of a divided discipline: rethinking the concept of cause in international relations theory. Review of International Studies 32(2): 189–216. Google Scholar | Crossref | ISI
[118] Morgenthau, H (1972) Science: Servant or Master? New York: New American Library. Google Scholar
[119] Jackson, P, Nexon, D (2013) International theory in a post-paradigmatic era: from substantive wagers to scientific ontologies. European Journal of International Relations 19(3): 543–565. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[120] Reus-Smit, C (2013) Beyond Metatheory? European Journal of International Relations 19(3): 589–608. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[121] Jahn, B (2017) Theorizing the political relevance of international relations theory. International Studies Quarterly 61(1): 64–77. Google Scholar
[122] Sylvester, C (2013) Experiencing the end and afterlives of international relations/Theory. European Journal of International Relations 19(3): 609–626. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[123] Lake, D (2011) Why ‘Isms’ are evil: theory, epistemology, and academic sects as impediments to understanding and progress. International Studies Quarterly 55(1): 1–16. Google Scholar
[124] Sil, R, Katzenstein, P (2008) Eclectic theorizing in the study and practice of international relations. In: Reus-Smit, C, Snidal, D (eds) The Oxford Handbook of International Relations. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Google Scholar
[125] Kurki, M (2011) The limitations of the critical edge: reflections on critical and philosophical IR scholarship today. Millennium 40(1): 129–146. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[126] Bennett, A (2013) The mother of all isms: causal mechanisms and structured pluralism in international relations theory. European Journal of International Relations 19(3): 459–481. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[127] Jahn, B (2017) Theorizing the political relevance of international relations theory. International Studies Quarterly 61(1): 64–77. Google Scholar
Reus-Smit, C (2013) Beyond Metatheory? European Journal of International Relations 19(3): 589–608. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
Nau, H (2011) No Alternative to “Isms”. International Studies Quarterly 55: 487–491. Google Scholar | Crossref | ISI
Lake, D (2011) Why ‘Isms’ are evil: theory, epistemology, and academic sects as impediments to understanding and progress. International Studies Quarterly 55(1): 1–16. Google Scholar
[128] Bennett, A (2013) The mother of all isms: causal mechanisms and structured pluralism in international relations theory. European Journal of International Relations 19(3): 459–481. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[129] Jackson, P, Nexon, D (2013) International theory in a post-paradigmatic era: from substantive wagers to scientific ontologies. European Journal of International Relations 19(3): 543–565. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[130] Mearsheimer, J, Walt, S (2013) Leaving theory behind: why simplistic hypothesis testing is bad for international relations. European Journal of International Relations 19(3): 427–57. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals
[131] Suganami, H (2013) Meta-Jackson: rethinking Patrick Thaddeus Jackson’s conduct of inquiry. Millennium 41(2): 248–269. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[132] Berenskötter, F (2018) Deep theorizing in international relations. European Journal of International Relations 24(4): 814–840. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[133] Id.
[134] Palmer, N (1980) The study of international relations in the United States: perspectives of half a century. International Studies Quarterly 24(3): 343–363. Google Scholar | Crossref
[135] Smith, S (2002) The United States and the discipline of international relations: “hegemonic country, hegemonic discipline”. International Studies Review 4(2): 67–85. Google Scholar | Crossref
Wendt, A (1999) Social Theory of International Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Google Scholar | Crossref
Adler, E (1997) Seizing the middle ground: constructivism in world politics, European Journal of International Relations 3(3): 319–363. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
Checkel, J (1998) The constructivist turn in international relations theory. World Politics 50(2): 324–348. Google Scholar | Crossref | ISI
[136] Dunne, T, Hansen, L, Wight, C (2013) The end of international relations theory? European Journal of International Relations 19(3): 405–425. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[137] Id.
[138] Id., 417.
[139] Hutchings, K (2019) Decolonizing global ethics: thinking with the Pluriverse. Ethics and International Affairs 33(2): 115–125. Google Scholar | Crossref
[140] Vasilaki, R (2012) Provincialising IR? deadlocks and prospects in post-Western IR theory. Millennium 41(1): 3–22. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[141] Matin, 2011: 365.
[142] Dunne, T, Hansen, L, Wight, C (2013) The end of international relations theory? European Journal of International Relations 19(3): 405–425. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[143] Hutchings, K (2019) Decolonizing global ethics: thinking with the Pluriverse. Ethics and International Affairs 33(2): 115–125. Google Scholar | Crossref
[144] Rosenberg, J (2016) International relations in the prison of political science. International Relations 30(2): 127–153. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[145] Jackson, P (2017) Out of one prison, into another? Comments on Rosenberg. International Relations 31(1): 81–84. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals
[146] Jackson, P (2011) The Conduct of Inquiry in International Relations: Philosophy of Science and Its Implications for the Study of World Politics. London: Routledge. Google Scholar
[147] Mouffe, C (1999) Deliberative democracy or agnostic pluralism? Social Research 66(3): 745–758. Google Scholar | ISI
[148] Eun, Y (2018) Beyond ‘the West/non-West Divide’ in IR: how to ensure dialogue as mutual learning. Chinese Journal of International Politics 11(4): 435–449. Google Scholar | Crossref
[149] Hutchings, K (2011) Dialogue between whom? The role of the West/ Non-West distinction in promoting global dialogue in IR. Millennium 39(3): 639–647. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[150] Lapid, J (2003) Through dialogue to engaged pluralism: the unfinished business of the third debate. International Studies Review 5(1): 128–131. Google Scholar | Crossref
[151] Morgenthau, H (1972) Science: Servant or Master? New York: New American Library. Google Scholar
[152] Jackson, P (2017) Out of one prison, into another? Comments on Rosenberg. International Relations 31(1): 81–84. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals
Tickner, A (2011) Dealing with difference: problems and possibilities for dialogue in international Relations. Millennium 39(3): 607–618. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
Dunne, T, Hansen, L, Wight, C (2013) The end of international relations theory? European Journal of International Relations 19(3): 405–425. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
Acharya, A (2014) Global international relations (IR) and regional worlds. International Studies Quarterly 58(4): 647–659. Google Scholar | Crossref | ISI
[153] Wolff, J, Zimmerman, L (2016) Between banyans and battle scenes: liberal norms, contestation, and the limits of critique. Review of International Studies 42(3): 513–534. Google Scholar | Crossref
Suganami, H (2013) Meta-Jackson: rethinking Patrick Thaddeus Jackson’s conduct of inquiry. Millennium 41(2): 248–269. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[154] Behr, H, Roesch, F (2012) Introduction. In: Behr, H, Roesch, F (eds) The Concept of the Political (trans. Vidal, M ). Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. Google Scholar
[155] Williams, M (2013) In the beginning: the international relations enlightenment and the ends of international relations theory. European Journal of International Relations 19(3): 647–665. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[156] Suganami, H (2013) Meta-Jackson: rethinking Patrick Thaddeus Jackson’s conduct of inquiry. Millennium 41(2): 248–269. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[157] Id.
[158] Waltz, K (1979) Theory of International Politics. Mass: Addison-Wesley. Google Scholar
[159] Bessner, D, Guilhot, N (2015) How realism waltzed off: liberalism and decision-making in Kenneth Waltz’s neorealism. International Security 40(2): 87–118. Google Scholar | Crossref | ISI
[160] Behr, H (2013) Security, politics and public discourse: a Morgenthauian approach. In: Bevir, M, Daddow, O, Hall, I (eds) Interpreting Global Security. London: Routledge. Google Scholar
[161] Id.
[162] Desch, M (2015) Technique trumps relevance: the professionalization of political science and the marginalization of security studies. Perspectives on Politics 13(2): 377–393. Google Scholar | Crossref
[163] Sjoberg, L (2015) Locating relevance in security studies. Perspectives on Politics 13(2): 396–398. Google Scholar | Crossref
Voeten, E (2015) Rigor is not the enemy of relevance. Perspectives on Politics 13(2): 402–403. Google Scholar | Crossref
[164] Acharya, A (2014) Global international relations (IR) and regional worlds. International Studies Quarterly 58(4): 647–659. Google Scholar | Crossref | ISIAcharya, 2018
Buzan, B (2016) Could IR be different? International Studies Review 18(1): 155–157. Google Scholar | Crossref
[165] Alejandro, A (2019) Western Dominance in International Relations? The Internationalisation of IR in Brazil and India. Abingdon Oxon: Routledge. Google Scholar
[166] Zhang, Y, Chang, T-C (2016) Constructing a Chinese School of International Relations: Ongoing Debates and Sociological Realities, Constructing a Chinese School of International Relations. Abington Oxon: Routledge. Google Scholar | Crossref
[167] Linklater, A (1992) The question of the next stage in international relations theory: a critical-theoretical point of view. Millennium 21(1): 77–98. Google Scholar | SAGE Journals | ISI
[168] Watanabe, A (2019) Japanese Geopolitics and the Western Imagination, Japanese Geopolitics and the Western Imagination. Cham: Palgrave Macmillan. Google Scholar | Crossref
[169] Çapan, ZG (2016) Re-Writing International Relations: History and Theory Beyond Eurocentrism in Turkey. London: Rowman and Littlefield. Google Scholar
[170] Parmar, I (2019) Global power shifts, diversity, and hierarchy in international politics. Ethics and International Affairs 33(2): 231–244. Google Scholar | Crossref
[171] Buzan, B (2016) Could IR be different? International Studies Review 18(1): 155–157. Google Scholar | Crossref
[172] Buzan, B (2018) How and how not to develop IR theory: lessons from core and periphery. Chinese Journal of International Politics 11(4): 391–414. Google Scholar | Crossref
[173] Behr, H, Roesch, F (2012) Introduction. In: Behr, H, Roesch, F (eds) The Concept of the Political (trans. Vidal, M ). Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. Google Scholar
Roesch, F (2014) Pouvoir, puissance, and politics: Hans Morgenthau’s dualistic concept of power? Review of International Studies 40(2): 349–365. Google Scholar | Crossref
[174] Morgenthau, H (1978) Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, 5th edn. New York: Alfred Knopf. Google Scholar
[175] Schweller, R (2017) Domestic politics and nationalism in East Asian Security. In: Ross, R, Tunsjø, Ø (eds) Strategic Adjustment and the Rise of China. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 15–40. Google Scholar
.